• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    On the Characteristics of Classical Natural Law

    2021-04-14 22:30:41ChengZhimin
    Contemporary Social Sciences 2021年2期

    Cheng Zhimin

    Hainan University

    Abstract: Classical natural law still retains its deep transcendental roots, i.e. ancient Greek cosmology, although it is no longer based on theodicy. The oldest meaning of the universe (kosmos) is not nature, but order. Therefore, the universe is larger than nature. Cosmology, which takes a holistic approach to everything, is superior to reason or ontology, which underlies modern natural law and is essentially a mechanistic worldview. Classical natural law does not regard reason as the ultimate cause to avoid the disconnection of “form” from “substance,” which is a disadvantage of modern thought resulting in a loss of regulative capacity. The eternal recurrence (ewige Wiederkehr) of natural law requires us to constantly revisit the idea of classical natural law in order to find a real footing for the salvation of reality.

    Keywords: natural law, divine law, cosmology, reason

    Unlike modern natural law, which is self-evidently rational, classical natural law exhibited inherent conflicts and struggles right from the very beginning and underwent a rather long process of integration before reluctantly coming into being under the name natural law. Thus, to modern people, natural law is the inherent law of the universe or reason, an objective standard for determining what is right and wrong, and a ready-made “higher law.” To ancient people, however, the term natural law itself was questionable,as behind it lay a paradox of choice concerning fundamental issues of human thought, such as rationality versus enlightenment, the sacred versus the secular, vindication of God versus vindication of man, ancestry versus mastery (or, in Confucian terms, “following the earlier kings” versus “following the later kings”), revolution versus conformity, democracy versus tyranny,necessity versus freedom, and will versus norm.

    How did the “nature-law” issue become inherently conflicting? Why did nature and law clash with each other in a particular historical period? What was the relationship between nature and law prior to the emergence of their conflict?

    Originally, all was under law (themis or nomos) and all natural beings (physis) in the universe were subordinate to law. In such a context, nature and law were inclusive and free from any conflict. Even with new meanings added, physis remained highly consistent with nomos in terms of purposiveness and sacredness and even retained original unity in terms of social or group functions, otherwise the later emergence of natural law would not have been possible. With the rise of reason, however, religious beliefs, which were the basis of “l(fā)aw,” became the target of attack. The nature-law conflict that emerged during that period was in fact first manifested as a fundamental conflict between reason and faith, or between religion and philosophy in the form of either safeguarding or rebelling against tradition. Using the nature of things as a weapon, the revolutionaries opposed the confinement of outdated dogmas and all nomos (which stood for norm).

    Recent studies of natural law slightly resemble classical natural law for being a “problem”itself. Yet, the respective problems they deal with are essentially different. The school of new natural law tries to counter legal positivism with the old nomos (or rather, classical natural law) “shields perceptions of the current world situation from the confusion of legal positivism”(Schmitt, 2006, p. 69. Cf; George, 1999, pp. 17ff), the erosion of skepticism, the poisoning of atheism and the resulting ethical relativism in absinkende Zeit, and to eventually allow us to escape extinction in the surge of nihilism. Nevertheless, the modern physics-based concept of physis is in nature a mechanistic cosmology, which has no place for natural law and leaves physis itself, the very foundation of natural law in ontology unsettled (to say nothing of the existence of the gods). As a result, “Thus positivism, which was now beginning its triumphal march, obtained its laurels all too easily, since it was indeed able to vanquish this historical form of a philosophy of law which called itself natural law, but not the idea itself of natural law”(Rommen, 1998, p. 96). Thus, however hard the academics try to revive natural law, it remains highly questionable whether they will manage to solve what they are trying to solve—that is the most fundamental issue facing the current study of natural law.

    Cosmology as the Basis of Classical Natural Law

    To the ancients, the idea of nature or universe itself was characterized by personality, which means it signified human emotions (pleasure, anger, sorrow and joy), will and purpose. Most importantly, as nature or universe was believed to have been divinely ordained or created, it was endowed with divinity.①Nature is purposeful, rather than accidental or spontaneous (Aristotle, The physic, n.d., 198b34-199a2). In this regard, similar ideas can be found in ancient Chinese philosophies. For example, Dong Zhongshu said, “Just like man, the heaven also has its own emotions (pleasure, anger, sorrow and joy). It is precisely this similarity that enables interaction and harmony between man and heaven ” (Dong, 1992, p. 341).In this way, natural law and divine law were connected by one similarity, namely cosmology. Heraclitus considered divine law to be a natural law reflected in the law and relevance of the universe, “His divine law is a law of nature, manifesting itself in cosmic regularities and reciprocities, the sun’s diurnal rotation, seasonal changes, and the cycle of life and death. It also appears to be natural, as distinct from human, law, with a universal,authoritative, and objective scope that civic laws can at best seek to approximate” (Long, 2005,p. 418). Natural law, which was close to divine law, was mainly reflected in the “continuous emergence of the new” in the universe. According to Heraclitus, natural law exists in the law of the universe, or can be understood as the law of the universe itself. By law of the universe,he meant “cosmic justice,” rather than “cosmic law.” Likewise, the idea of natural law did not appear as a form of normative integration in the golden age of the ancient Greek civilization,when dike (justice) was preferred to nomos (although the term dike was of judicial significance).The “natural justice” in ancient Greek sense corresponded to the so-called “natural law” which appeared later (Plato, The Republic, n.d., 501b, The Laws, n.d., 889d-890d, Timaeus, n.d., 83e4-5;Thucydides, The History of the Peloponnesian War, n.d., 5.105; Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, n.d.,1134b-1135a).

    In the view of the ancients, the universe itself, which includes the sun, the moon and the stars, and witnesses the lapse of seasons and years, is sufficient to prove the existence of the gods (Plato, ca. 360 B.C.E., The Laws, 885e-886a). The gods control the repeated changes of nature (Plato, ca. 360 B.C.E., The Laws, 715e-716a); the fundamental law for the harmonious coexistence of all things in the universe should be the goal of mankind, or should at least make man devout and kind (Plato, Epinomis 990a; Cicero, On the Laws. 2.16, On the Commonwealth 1.26, 6.20-29, 2.16). It was precisely in the context of divine law that Plato sought support for cosmology.

    Unlike the Hebrew God who created everything, the ancient Greek gods were responsible only for “ordering” the universe. The word theos (gods) in ancient Greek came from tithemi(meaning “to put”). Originally, everything was out of order. It was the gods that “put things in order” (die-kosm-ēsen), integrated them into a whole, namely, the universe (kosmos) and endowed the whole world with sacredness, naturalness, purposiveness and morality (Plato,Timaeus, 69c). In ancient Greek, both “the universe” and “order” were referred to as kosmos.Now that kosmos covered “nature” and “l(fā)aw”, there was “natural law” in the kosmos.

    Cicero echoed the idea more bluntly, “The immortal gods implanted souls in human bodies so as to have beings who would care for the earth and who, while contemplating the celestial order (caelestium ordinem), would imitate it in the moderation and consistency (constantia)of their lives” (Cicero, trans. 1923). Constantia is eternity, which is also one of the essentials of natural law. The movement of celestial bodies and the change of seasons are the law of“nature,” and also the law that man should imitate (Cicero, ca. 352 B.C.E., On the laws 1.61,2.16). Obedience to “obey this celestial order (caelesti descriptioni), the divine mind and the all-powerful god” (Cicero, ca. 52 On the Laws 1.23) is obedience to natural law and divine law,for the basis of natural law is celestial regency. Similar ideas can be found in ancient Chinese philosophy, too. Mozi once said, “What then should be taken as the standard in government?Nothing better than following Heaven. Heaven is all-inclusive and impartial in its activities,abundant and unceasing in its blessings, and lasting and untiring in its guidance. And, so,when the sage-kings had accepted Heaven as their standard, they measured every action and enterprise by Heaven. What Heaven desired they would carry out, what Heaven abominated they refrained from” (Mozi, Fayi). Laozi held that “the ‘Tao’ (the divine law) follows nature”(Laozi, Laozi) because “Heaven is the divine law, and the divine law is eternal” (Laozi, Laozi).Later, Dong Zhongshu advocated “following the laws of Heaven and nature” (Dong, n.d.).

    Cosmology as the basis of classical natural law was not debated in ancient times. But in modern times, cosmology may sound old-fashioned, unscientific or even superstitious to people, who may thus oppose classical natural law and eventually make (classical) natural law no longer possible. Or to flip it around, with cosmology as a divine teleology, along with the holistic mindset abandoned by modern people, natural law loses ground and inevitably comes to an end. Under such circumstances, a careful examination of the positive senses and possible limits of classical cosmology is needed.

    From a contemporary perspective, classic natural law is associated with an antiquated classical cosmology, which, however, seems to have been found untrue by the huge achievements of modern science. Is that true? Leo Strauss did not think so, holding that modern natural sciences, however successful they become, had no impact on our understanding of“what is human in man” at all. Modern natural sciences no longer see the universe and human nature as “the whole,” making “man as man wholly unintelligible.” “The whole is of mysterious character, and man’s openness to the whole contains the quest for cosmology” (Strauss, 1988,p. 39). Classical cosmology is an organic and holistic view, while modern cosmology is an outcome of mechanical technology. To the ancient Greeks, “heaven and earth and gods and men are bound together by communion and friendship, orderliness, temperance, and justice, and it is for that reason they call this Whole a Cosmos” (Plato, ca. 380 B.C.E., 508a). This view was proposed some 2,000 years earlier than das Geviert, which was proposed by Martin Heidegger with great effort. From a holistic perspective, cosmology is more brilliant than ontology. But the general history of philosophy wrongly assumes it is a historical progress to shift from cosmology to ontology, and to epistemology and the study of speech.

    Without a holistic cosmology, man, the gods and the universe would be separated from each other and have no relevance to each other; everything would turn into an atomic natural element; the meaning of life would be buried in “science.” What makes classical cosmology superior to modern cosmology is that classical cosmology retains a concern for humanity.When Descartes’ universe replaced Aristotle’s, and when a universe made up of nature was replaced by a vast thing—the extension (whose components, arrangement and reorganization allowed itself to be handled perfectly in a mathematical way), we had to cope with a picture of the world in which the teleological elements are as irrelevant as the elements of color and taste are to geometry (Simon, 2016, p. 91). This mechanistic view of the universe, which started from Descartes, was already common in Plato’s time (Plato, ca. 360 B.C.E., Laws 889b-c). It goes without saying that there can be no such thing as natural law in a thoroughly mechanistic universe (Simon, 2016, p. 93).①The natural teleology held by Morelly in Code of Nature (1982, p. 21) is in fact a mechanistic view of nature (p. 24). Given that, Morelly’s citation of Cicero was essentially a misunderstanding. Strauss criticized the mechanistic view of the universe but defended Aristotle’s teleological view of the universe (Strauss,2003, p. 8).Strauss thus asked, “What is wrong with cosmology? What is wrong with man’s attempt to find his bearing on the basis of what is apparent to him as a man?”(Strauss, 1997, p. 371). The contemplation of the divine principle in classical philosophy is not a value-neutral, objective study purely in search of knowledge, but a basis “by which we are led to the right conduct” (Strauss, 1997, p. 373). The fundamental teaching of classical thought is“know thyself,” which is primarily about finding one’s place in the universe—one of the most important teachings of classical cosmology and its resulting theory of natural law.

    The Place of Reason in Classical Natural Law

    In ancient times, Natural law is a “divine gift,” and as long as natural law exists, it seems to be natural and rightful. Even so, natural law itself is not self-evident. Therefore, our understanding of natural law requires the intervention of human reason. Although natural law in Ulpian’s term refers to something that nature gave to all living things (natura omnia animalia docuit) (Justinian, 1989, p. 6), there is no doubt that only humans can experience and even participate in the laws of the universe. After all, of all creatures, only humans have reason. This close association of reason with natural law can easily lead to the misconception that natural law, which can only be understood through reason, is nothing more than a product of reason.Such a misconception, however, is made by modern natural law.②Pound’s understanding of natural law in Roman law is very modern, as the natural law in his vision is in fact an equivalent to modern natural law. “Natural law is a discursive legal style……It originates from reason and is constructed in a philosophical way. The creative application of this ideal helps outline the characteristics of the classical Roman law-governed era” (Pound, 2004, p. 36).Besides, even if reason and natural law can hardly be separated from each other, there is still a world of difference between the “reason” of today and the “reason” in ancient times in terms of meaning and limit.

    Reason: Not the Ultimate Cause

    The ancients considered rational beings more noble than irrational beings. To them, the gods are the noblest of all beings and therefore deservedly possess absolute reason. The goal of man is to use reason or rationality as a means to find ways to “resemble the gods,” i.e., to move towards or approach divinity and achieve perfection as much as possible, which is known as natural law (Plato, Timaeus, 90c6-d7). Cicero argued, “Those who have been given reason by nature have also been given right reason, and therefore law too, which is right reason in commands and prohibitions; and if they have been given law, then they have been given justice too” (Cicero, Ca. 360 B.C.E., On the Laws, 1.33). Natural reason (naturalis ratio) reveals law①Huang Feng, translator of Gai institutiones (Chinese edition) translated naturalis ratio into “natural reason” in Chinese (Gaius, 1996, p. 2).and, more importantly, it is in itself lex divina et humana (Cicero, On obligations, n.d, 3.23, On divination, n.d., 1.90, 1.30, 2.37; Plato, Minos, n.d., 316b5, Theaetetus, n.d., 172b, 177d; Aristotle,Rhetoric, n.d., 1375a31-b5).

    According to the theory of classical natural law, “Law is the highest reason, rooted in nature……when this same reason is secured and established in the human mind (mente), it is law” (Cicero, ca. 360 B.C.E., On the Laws, 1.18); “virtue evidently consists in perfect reason and this certainly resides in nature” (Cicero, ca. 360 B.C.E., On the Laws, 1.25, 56). The “reason”here does not refer to anyone’s reason, or human reason, but a “universal” reason. Natural law is more of an outcome of divine reason. The theory of modern natural law, however, relies on individualistic rationalism, with the result that abstract humanity, rather than divinity, becomes the basis of natural law. Hugo Grotius made it clear that “the mother of right—that is, of natural law—is human nature” (Grotius, p. 1749; Pound, 2004, p. 48).②In Finnis’ view, Aristotle (Metaphysics, n.d., 1070a12, 1015a14-15) and Aquinas had built natural law on human nature (Finnis, 2011, p. 103).His words marked a watershed.“For henceforth not God’s essence, but human nature, viewed existentially as well as merely in the abstract, would be regarded as the source of natural law” (Rommen, 2007, p. 88). As a result, the basis of natural law becomes an imagined state of nature. But Thomas Aquinas long ago warned, “It does not suffice that it advance from first principles implanted by nature”(Aquinas, 2000, p. 12).

    While sacred, reason is not supreme and is essentially a means to the end of virtue. Reason has a significant capacity to enable an understanding of natural law, but its capacity is bound to be limited. In other words, classical natural law recognizes that law comes from “right reason,” but reason is not the ultimate cause, which comes from the divine. Without the divine,there would be nothing in the universe more remarkable than man. This assumption, i.e. nonexistence of the divine, is summae adrogantiae and even sane adrogantis. Yet, this invalid assumption became a reliable logical premise (non esse Deum) to Grotius.

    Aquinas proclaimed, “Human reason is not, of itself, the rule of things: but the principles impressed on it by nature, are general rules and measures of all things relating to human conduct, whereof the natural reason is the rule and measure, although it is not the measure of things that are from nature” (Aquinas, 2016, p. 20). Thus, the reason which classical natural law resorts to is far from (modern) rationalism. “The proud spirit of modern rationalism is lacking.There is no assertion of man’s self-sufficiency and inherent perfection. There is no vindication of abstract ‘rights’ nor of the autonomy of the individual as the ultimate source of all laws and of all standards” (D’Entreves, 2008, pp. 50-51). In the ancients’ view, great reason in itself needs to be supported or even proved by other evidence; reason is not, after all, ultimate. And“there is in (classical nature law) no trace whatever of the extravagances of the rationalistic natural law current in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries” (Rommen, 2007, p. 49). The difference between classical natural law and modern natural law lies in the fact that the former denies natural law to be an outcome of reason, while the latter, having eliminated deism, can only base natural law on reason and consider natural law to be an outcome of self-deduction through speculative reason (Kant, 1781, Axx, Bxiii, B780).

    The Finitude of Reason

    Any finite being in this world features a paradoxical duality, with both advantages and disadvantages. To the ancients, god-given reason is admittedly keen (Cicero, On moral ends,5.57). Yet, wrong application of reason makes one suffer the consequences. After all, no bad thing is the masterwork of bona ratio (Cicero, On divination, 3.71). To the ancients, reason is great and therefore needs to be treated with more caution. “The greater and more divine their superiority, the greater their need of assiduous care. And so reason if well employed (adhibita)sees clearly what is best; if left neglected it is entangled in a multitude of deceptions.” (Cicero,Tusculan disputations, 4.58). Elsewhere, Cicero thoroughly reflected on the finitude of reason:

    God gives us only reason, assuming that in fact he does; whether it is good or bad depends on ourselves. When reason is bestowed upon a person by the gods’ gift, it is not analogous to a bequest left to us, for if they had wished to harm us what better could they have bestowed on mankind? If reason does not underlie injustice, lack of restraint and cowardice, from what seeds would these vices sprout? (Cicero, On the nature of the gods, 3.71)

    The evil in the world is also the “masterwork” of reason. Given that, reason is not omnipotent, let alone the best. In essence, reason is not the god. In fact, Socrates had long since sharply criticized the then roaring wave of rationalism. He was originally convinced by Anaxagoras’ theory of mind (nous), but later discovered this theory to be a hubristic nonsense.According to Socrates, Anaxagoras’ theory, which held that mind organizes (diakosmōn) and arranges (kosmein) all things, including the universe (kosmos), was theoretically groundless and sacrilegious. That was why Socrates took a different route and started his famous “second voyage” (Socrates, Phaedo. 97c-99d). Modern scholars have also recognized that reason can lead man astray. To them, it is no surprise that under such circumstances this reason turned into one of the most dangerous tools of vices and took the wrong turning (Morelly, 1982, p. 30).

    Reason is often compared to the sun, for it enables us to see everything more clearly, “but we cannot stare at the sun long, for the light would ruin our eyes” (Plato, Phaedo, 99d5-7).The sun (reason) can nourish all things. But excessive sun exposure can cause a “house fire.”There are some modern thinkers “having their eyes hurt” due to their addiction to reason. It has become an irreversible fact that their over-amplification of the brilliance of reason gave rise to an extensive crisis in modern philosophy. The explanation is as follows, “The rationalism of the Encyclopedists, making of natural law no longer an offspring of creative wisdom but a revelation of reason unto itself, transformed natural law into a code of absolute and universal justice inscribed in nature and deciphered by reason as an ensemble of geometric theorems or speculative data” (Maritain, 2009, pp. 74-75).

    Suarez, Grotius, Descartes and Pufendorf endowed reason with infinite power, making the objective order of all things (ordo rerum) and also natural law, which was based on it,superfluous. To them, human reason was supreme; while to ordinary people, their ego and everything related to it were directly guaranteed via “I think.” Man becomes an angel because he has reason. Modern rational epistemology is angelic epistemology in essence. “Rationalism soon made human reason and its innate ideas the measure of what is. Human reason could now indulge in the uncontrolled construction of systems that have characterized the natural law of rationalism” (Rommen, 2007, pp. 80-81). Nevertheless, this anthroposophical angelism was bound to degenerate, and reason would not be able to support human morality and would eventually be taken over by economic status. Modern scholars such as John Finnis, having abandoned metaphysics, tried to develop a doctrine of natural law without nature. The natural law in the age of naturalism, individualism, radicalism and rationalism eventually became the founder and gravedigger of modern thoughts.

    The Form and Substance of Natural Law

    In classical thought, reason is an external cognitive faculty with specific connotations.Natural law is right reason, whose rightness is reflected in its guidance to virtue. Thus, virtue is the connotation of reason and is also the main target of classical natural law (Laertius, Lives of eminent philosophers, 7.94). Natural law is called the “teacher of life” because it is in itself the leges vivendi et disciplinam or vivendi doctrina (Cicero, ca. 360 B.C.E., On the Laws, 1.57, 1.58)Strauss concluded, “Natural law directs man toward his perfection, the perfection of a rational and social animal; it is ‘the guide of life and the teacher of the duties’ (Cicero, On the nature of the gods, 1.40); it is the dictate of reason regarding human life. Thus, the virtuous life as choiceworthy for its own sake comes to be understood as compliance with natural law—with a law,and hence as a life of obedience. Inversely, the content of natural law is the whole of virtue”(Strauss, 1983, p. 141).

    Classical natural law values reason, but it ultimately aims at virtue and happiness in order to safeguard human interests (Cicero, On obligations, 3.31). If such content is still not deemed substantive enough, the classical view of reason and its implicated natural law also have concrete provisions concerning reverence for the gods, defense of mother country, filial devotion to parents, and loyalty to brothers and friends. “If nature does not ratify law, then all the virtues may lose their sway. For what becomes of generosity, patriotism, or friendship?Where will the desire of benefitting our neighbors, or the gratitude that acknowledges kindness,be able to exist at all? For all these virtues proceed from our natural inclination to love mankind. And this is the true basis of justice, and without this not only the mutual charities of men, but the religious services of the gods, would be at an end” (Cicero, Ca. 360 B.C.E.,On the Laws., 1.43). All these virtues (reverence, sincerity, loyalty, filial piety, fraternity and kindheartedness) are the inherent connotations of classical natural law or classical rationality.

    Through continued deification of its content, reason was eventually brought to its climax by Kant and Hegel, to whom everything could be deduction from reason. “Human reason now becomes the sovereign architect of the order of knowledge; it becomes the measure of things.The objective basis of natural law, the ordo rerum and the eternal law, has vanished. What was termed natural law is a series of conclusions drawn from the categorical imperative and from the regulative ideas of practical reason, not from the objective and constitutive ordo rerum”(Rommen, 1998, p. 78). The true meaning of the “our faculty of understanding is the primary source of nature’s lawfulness” is that human reason is the source of natural law. Natural law is primarily about safeguarding free will. The “categorical imperative” or “definitive imperative”of natural law becomes an empty form. “Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law” (Kant, 1997, p. 31). The“categorical imperative” of this universal natural law (allgemeinen Naturgesetze) seems similar to the quote by Confucius—“Do not do unto others what you do not want done unto you”(Confucius, Duke Ling of Wei, The analects of Confucius). But Confucius also specified what must be obeyed in conduct and behavior beyond this formal principle, while Kant did not teach anything substantive in this rational “categorical imperative.”

    Johann Gottlieb Fichte also expressed an idea similar to Kant’s “categorical imperative.”He said, “The principle of any judgment of right is that each is to limi his freedom, the sphere of his free actions, through the concept of the freedom of the other (so that the other, as free in general, can exist as well)” (Fichte, 2000, p. 102). But mankind had struggled in this vast ocean of “freedom” for centuries before a narrow escape from drowning. They became more and more aware of the fact that freedom, although being the basis of modern natural law, has no substance at all. If not carefully distinguished, concepts like freedom, equality, natural state,will and absolute rights can be a mirage leading to nowhere.

    Modern natural law is based on the scientific “natural law” or “l(fā)aw of nature” (Gierke, 1934,p. 35)①According to Gierke (1934, p. 35), a leading scholar of natural law, it was the “l(fā)aw of nature” that led to the disintegration of the medieval concept of natural law. John Locke directly applied “l(fā)aw of nature” in the sense of natural law (Locke, 2014).. But unfortunately, “the ‘natural law’ of the natural sciences only denotes a calculable function without substance” (Schmitt, 2006, p. 72). Just like philosophical positivism, scientific natural law has no interest in core issues such as “origin” and “root” and therefore becomes homeless and rootless. Pufendorf (and Hobbes) and Cicero all understood natural law as an outcome of “right reason.” Cicero specified what reason was right (Cicero, On obligations),while Pufendorf just mentioned this “right reason” in vague terms (Buckle, 2014, p. 131).Similarly, in Kant’s view, “The impersonal, formal, categorical imperative takes the place of the eternal law. The natural law, therefore, as part of the lex naturalis, is no longer connected with the eternal law, for the very reason that it can no longer be understood as part of the lex naturalis, of the rational moral law. Furthermore, not enforceability but external physical force is directly and necessarily included in the concept of law” (Rommen, 1998, p. 90). Kant’s rational formalist argument prevented him from developing a doctrine of substantive value. To this end, Max Scheler competed a lengthy critique of Kant’s pure formalism (Scheler, 2011, pp.8-9, p. 113).①Scheler once made a vicious comment on Kant. According to Scheler, Kant’s ethics is not half right or all wrong, but the “devil’s words” (Scheler, 1999, p.715). The fundamental reason may lie in the fact that Kant was under the direct influence of Grotius, Pufendorf and Thomasius. Worst of all, neither Kant nor Pufendorf had any real understanding of classical natural law. “Or was it not fateful that Pufendorf was well acquainted with scarcely a single Greek or Scholastic, and that Kant, the watershed from which flow so many and such varied streams of modern thought, knew Aristotle and St. Thomas only from a very imperfect history of philosophy?” (Rommen, 2007. p. 85). This was indeed an “extremely fateful fact.” Leibniz’s critique of Pufendorf can be found in Natural Law and the Theory of Property: Grotius to Hume (Buckle, 2014, p. 55) and The Natural Law: A Study in Legal and Social History and Philosophy (Rommen,2007, p. 88).In this way, natural law ceased to have any substantive content and eventually came to an end.

    Conclusion

    The shift from divine law to natural law seems to be an inevitable process, which was already marked in ancient Greece: “The quest for the beginning, for the first things, becomes now the philosophic or scientific analysis of the cosmos; the place of the divine law, in the traditional sense of the term, where it is a code traced to a personal god, is replaced by a natural order, which may even be called, as it was later to be called, a natural law—or at any rate,to use a wider term, a natural morality. So the divine law, in the real and strict sense of the term, is only the starting point, the absolutely essential starting point, for Greek philosophy,but it is abandoned in the process. And if it is accepted by Greek philosophy, it is accepted only politically, meaning for the education of the many, and not as something which stands independently” (Strauss, 1989, p. 256). Later, divine law became a theoretical guarantee or an ideological irrelevance, which was perhaps also an inevitable trend. Unlike classical natural law, which relied on reason while being well aware of the perils of reason, modern natural law,after “executing deism” (Heine, 2007, p. 78), had no alternative but to leave natural law, or even the entire spiritual world to reason.

    Although the separation of divine and natural law had already occurred to Cicero, the two did not drift apart. In modern times, Hobbes, who emphasized the distinction between ius and lex (Hobbes, Leviathan, 1.14), distinguished natural rights from natural law, which became no more than a theoretical guarantee for natural rights. With the substantive theory of natural law on the wane, when talking about natural law, people were in fact talking about natural rights.Thus, natural law (lex naturalis) evolved into natural rights (ius naturale), or to say, natural law was replaced by natural rights, which marked the ultimate victory of “anthropolodicy.” After the American Revolution and the French Revolution, natural law as a disguise was dropped and natural rights were openly pursued. In particular, the right to self-preservation became an unconditional and absolute basis of natural law (Strauss, 2003, p. 185; Hobbes, 2003, p. 8, p.15)—(Never expected) the quality of thought degenerated to such a point. Blaise Pascal said,“Doubtless there are natural laws, but this fine reason having been corrupted, it corrupted everything” (Pascal, 2004).

    The result or manifestation of the corruption of reason is that “l(fā)aw” becomes “right”and that “nature” becomes “world” and “resources.” Once rational natural law is faced with widespread skepticism, the entire world of thought will fall into a new round of skepticism,historicism and nihilism, which again need to be remedied by a newly emerged “new natural law.” Natural law itself is in an “eternal cycle” or perpetual transition. As Heinrich Rommen put it, “Yet it has always come back into jurisprudence whenever the human mind, weary of the unsatisfying hunt for mere facts, has again turned to metaphysics, queen of the sciences”(Rommen, 1998, p.28)①Its original German version is entitled Die ewige Wiederkehr des Naturrechts (Leipzig: Verlag Jakob Hegner, 1936), whose literal translation into English should be the Eternal Recurrence of Natural Law.. In this regard, we are far less optimistic than Rommen was, as the many revivals of natural law in history were not Nietzsche’s ewige Wiederkehr, but Schmitt’s absinkende.

    The revival of natural law in modern times may end up being a game of self-deconstruction without full awareness of its problems. This game, along with modern relativism, cynicism,historicism, skepticism and nihilism, forebodes mankind’s spiritual decay. Against such a backdrop, a re-examination of classical natural law is not necessarily a “sovereign remedy,”but it can at least temporarily break the spell of ewige Wiederkehr and allow natural law to truly return to nature in the cosmological sense. Only in this way can treatment, redemption or other alternatives possibly be found.

    成年人午夜在线观看视频| 欧美 亚洲 国产 日韩一| 精品一区在线观看国产| 亚洲av成人精品一二三区| 国产黄频视频在线观看| 制服诱惑二区| 日韩人妻高清精品专区| 在线观看人妻少妇| 亚洲成人一二三区av| 三级国产精品片| 亚洲欧美中文字幕日韩二区| 99九九在线精品视频| 国产高清国产精品国产三级| 大片电影免费在线观看免费| 午夜av观看不卡| 日产精品乱码卡一卡2卡三| 亚洲一区二区三区欧美精品| 日本-黄色视频高清免费观看| 亚洲精品美女久久av网站| 亚洲人成网站在线观看播放| 青春草视频在线免费观看| 亚洲精品乱码久久久v下载方式| 日韩 亚洲 欧美在线| 久久 成人 亚洲| 91久久精品国产一区二区三区| 亚洲精品aⅴ在线观看| 亚洲精品一区蜜桃| 啦啦啦中文免费视频观看日本| 中文欧美无线码| 高清视频免费观看一区二区| 最近的中文字幕免费完整| 成人无遮挡网站| 九色成人免费人妻av| 九九久久精品国产亚洲av麻豆| 久久热精品热| 国产成人精品久久久久久| 哪个播放器可以免费观看大片| 欧美日韩一区二区视频在线观看视频在线| 看免费成人av毛片| 国产精品一区二区三区四区免费观看| 99re6热这里在线精品视频| 蜜桃在线观看..| 亚洲在久久综合| 久久鲁丝午夜福利片| 久久久久国产网址| 伦理电影大哥的女人| 人人妻人人爽人人添夜夜欢视频| 久久狼人影院| 青春草视频在线免费观看| 亚洲欧美成人精品一区二区| 欧美变态另类bdsm刘玥| 亚洲第一av免费看| 亚洲欧美色中文字幕在线| 久久久久久久亚洲中文字幕| 国产欧美日韩一区二区三区在线 | 内地一区二区视频在线| 日本黄色片子视频| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区| 国产成人aa在线观看| 久久精品久久久久久久性| 嘟嘟电影网在线观看| 中文字幕制服av| 中文字幕亚洲精品专区| 国产精品蜜桃在线观看| 精品人妻一区二区三区麻豆| 欧美精品高潮呻吟av久久| 亚洲欧美色中文字幕在线| 亚洲三级黄色毛片| 美女中出高潮动态图| 美女中出高潮动态图| 色5月婷婷丁香| 日韩在线高清观看一区二区三区| 久久婷婷青草| 尾随美女入室| 成人午夜精彩视频在线观看| 人妻一区二区av| 一个人看视频在线观看www免费| 91精品一卡2卡3卡4卡| 美女内射精品一级片tv| 黄色毛片三级朝国网站| 高清不卡的av网站| 亚洲欧美清纯卡通| 一区二区三区乱码不卡18| 日韩免费高清中文字幕av| 丝袜脚勾引网站| 欧美3d第一页| 日本欧美视频一区| 国产成人精品一,二区| 精品亚洲成国产av| 久久久久久久国产电影| 久久精品国产亚洲av天美| 三上悠亚av全集在线观看| 如何舔出高潮| 三级国产精品片| 欧美亚洲日本最大视频资源| 精品亚洲乱码少妇综合久久| 精品亚洲成a人片在线观看| 中文字幕久久专区| 成年女人在线观看亚洲视频| 国产精品不卡视频一区二区| 久久国产精品男人的天堂亚洲 | 三级国产精品片| 超碰97精品在线观看| 亚洲精品乱码久久久v下载方式| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| 美女视频免费永久观看网站| 熟妇人妻不卡中文字幕| 一级爰片在线观看| 一区二区日韩欧美中文字幕 | 一本大道久久a久久精品| 国产片特级美女逼逼视频| 狂野欧美激情性bbbbbb| 妹子高潮喷水视频| 久久精品国产鲁丝片午夜精品| 国产精品久久久久久精品古装| 蜜桃国产av成人99| 成人二区视频| 自线自在国产av| 国产日韩欧美在线精品| av在线老鸭窝| 国产色婷婷99| 91精品三级在线观看| 在线天堂最新版资源| 黑丝袜美女国产一区| 亚洲中文av在线| 寂寞人妻少妇视频99o| 亚洲精品久久久久久婷婷小说| 亚洲国产精品一区二区三区在线| 满18在线观看网站| 亚洲精品自拍成人| 欧美精品一区二区免费开放| 日本wwww免费看| 亚洲一级一片aⅴ在线观看| 国产亚洲欧美精品永久| 丰满乱子伦码专区| 天美传媒精品一区二区| 91在线精品国自产拍蜜月| 一级毛片我不卡| 51国产日韩欧美| av女优亚洲男人天堂| videossex国产| 日韩 亚洲 欧美在线| 亚洲精品第二区| 人妻系列 视频| 999精品在线视频| 十八禁高潮呻吟视频| 欧美变态另类bdsm刘玥| 精品酒店卫生间| 国产成人精品无人区| 一级,二级,三级黄色视频| 又大又黄又爽视频免费| 又粗又硬又长又爽又黄的视频| 一边亲一边摸免费视频| 啦啦啦视频在线资源免费观看| 亚洲国产最新在线播放| 日本黄色片子视频| 欧美日韩亚洲高清精品| av在线老鸭窝| 午夜视频国产福利| 亚洲在久久综合| 日本-黄色视频高清免费观看| 18在线观看网站| 国产国拍精品亚洲av在线观看| 国产精品一区二区在线不卡| 性色avwww在线观看| 久久精品国产亚洲网站| 在线亚洲精品国产二区图片欧美 | 超色免费av| 一本色道久久久久久精品综合| 最近最新中文字幕免费大全7| 欧美性感艳星| 国产精品久久久久久av不卡| 热99国产精品久久久久久7| 久久久久久久大尺度免费视频| 成人午夜精彩视频在线观看| 亚洲久久久国产精品| 午夜福利网站1000一区二区三区| 日本av免费视频播放| 夫妻午夜视频| 精品久久久精品久久久| xxxhd国产人妻xxx| 丝袜美足系列| 三上悠亚av全集在线观看| 18+在线观看网站| 国产欧美亚洲国产| 欧美精品人与动牲交sv欧美| 一区二区av电影网| 色哟哟·www| 啦啦啦中文免费视频观看日本| 亚洲精品日本国产第一区| 性色av一级| 青春草视频在线免费观看| 国产成人一区二区在线| 亚洲成色77777| 午夜av观看不卡| 男女国产视频网站| 一本大道久久a久久精品| 亚洲精品乱码久久久v下载方式| 精品久久久噜噜| 亚洲精品一二三| 色网站视频免费| 国产熟女午夜一区二区三区 | 久热久热在线精品观看| 久久国产精品男人的天堂亚洲 | 女人久久www免费人成看片| 伊人亚洲综合成人网| 精品久久久久久电影网| 亚洲欧洲精品一区二区精品久久久 | 国产爽快片一区二区三区| 亚洲精品一区蜜桃| 国产精品人妻久久久久久| 人妻 亚洲 视频| 欧美激情国产日韩精品一区| 制服丝袜香蕉在线| 最黄视频免费看| 搡老乐熟女国产| 日韩亚洲欧美综合| 国产无遮挡羞羞视频在线观看| 久久精品国产鲁丝片午夜精品| 97超碰精品成人国产| 满18在线观看网站| 国产伦精品一区二区三区视频9| 多毛熟女@视频| 简卡轻食公司| 午夜激情福利司机影院| 亚洲国产精品国产精品| 一个人看视频在线观看www免费| 高清午夜精品一区二区三区| 久久精品国产自在天天线| 欧美国产精品一级二级三级| 国产精品熟女久久久久浪| 国产乱人偷精品视频| 高清视频免费观看一区二区| 亚洲欧美一区二区三区黑人 | 免费看av在线观看网站| 少妇精品久久久久久久| 伦理电影大哥的女人| 欧美日韩在线观看h| 午夜久久久在线观看| 青青草视频在线视频观看| 国产精品一区www在线观看| 久久国产精品男人的天堂亚洲 | 国产精品一区二区三区四区免费观看| 国产成人精品无人区| 国产精品秋霞免费鲁丝片| 欧美日韩视频高清一区二区三区二| 色婷婷久久久亚洲欧美| 中文字幕免费在线视频6| av专区在线播放| videosex国产| 午夜av观看不卡| 久久ye,这里只有精品| 最后的刺客免费高清国语| 久久精品久久久久久久性| av视频免费观看在线观看| 亚洲欧美精品自产自拍| 我的女老师完整版在线观看| 91在线精品国自产拍蜜月| 热re99久久精品国产66热6| a级片在线免费高清观看视频| 夫妻性生交免费视频一级片| 国产一区二区在线观看日韩| 欧美国产精品一级二级三级| 亚洲四区av| 99热这里只有精品一区| 久热这里只有精品99| 欧美精品人与动牲交sv欧美| av又黄又爽大尺度在线免费看| 免费av中文字幕在线| 在现免费观看毛片| 女的被弄到高潮叫床怎么办| 亚洲精品美女久久av网站| 国产精品偷伦视频观看了| 人人澡人人妻人| 欧美成人精品欧美一级黄| 久久久久国产网址| 国产国语露脸激情在线看| 国精品久久久久久国模美| 特大巨黑吊av在线直播| 女人久久www免费人成看片| 一区二区av电影网| 男男h啪啪无遮挡| 内地一区二区视频在线| 亚洲,欧美,日韩| 国产精品偷伦视频观看了| 免费观看无遮挡的男女| av黄色大香蕉| 国产白丝娇喘喷水9色精品| 亚洲美女黄色视频免费看| 青春草亚洲视频在线观看| 欧美亚洲日本最大视频资源| 欧美激情 高清一区二区三区| 尾随美女入室| 寂寞人妻少妇视频99o| 亚洲欧洲日产国产| 成年人午夜在线观看视频| 在线观看免费视频网站a站| 午夜福利在线观看免费完整高清在| 日本wwww免费看| 99久久精品国产国产毛片| 精品亚洲成a人片在线观看| 久久人妻熟女aⅴ| 大码成人一级视频| 国产精品99久久99久久久不卡 | 97超碰精品成人国产| 日韩一本色道免费dvd| 免费久久久久久久精品成人欧美视频 | 老司机影院毛片| 99久久中文字幕三级久久日本| 国语对白做爰xxxⅹ性视频网站| 久久精品国产a三级三级三级| 人妻制服诱惑在线中文字幕| 亚洲天堂av无毛| 黄色毛片三级朝国网站| 丝瓜视频免费看黄片| 国产免费现黄频在线看| 日韩三级伦理在线观看| 99久国产av精品国产电影| 国产成人精品一,二区| 国产精品 国内视频| 中文字幕最新亚洲高清| 国产精品蜜桃在线观看| 老司机影院毛片| 777米奇影视久久| 一边摸一边做爽爽视频免费| 欧美激情 高清一区二区三区| 日韩一本色道免费dvd| 亚洲欧洲精品一区二区精品久久久 | 久久免费观看电影| 精品久久久久久久久av| 在现免费观看毛片| 日韩视频在线欧美| 国产永久视频网站| av在线播放精品| 高清毛片免费看| 高清午夜精品一区二区三区| 一级片'在线观看视频| 麻豆精品久久久久久蜜桃| 久久久欧美国产精品| 国产午夜精品久久久久久一区二区三区| 久久99热这里只频精品6学生| 飞空精品影院首页| 国产成人freesex在线| 观看av在线不卡| 性色avwww在线观看| 十八禁高潮呻吟视频| 肉色欧美久久久久久久蜜桃| 多毛熟女@视频| 亚洲精品国产av蜜桃| 精品国产一区二区三区久久久樱花| 国产极品粉嫩免费观看在线 | 国产精品久久久久久久久免| 九草在线视频观看| 精品午夜福利在线看| 99热全是精品| 免费高清在线观看日韩| 色哟哟·www| 日韩一区二区三区影片| av有码第一页| 高清av免费在线| 另类精品久久| 美女脱内裤让男人舔精品视频| 一级片'在线观看视频| 热re99久久精品国产66热6| 国产高清不卡午夜福利| 各种免费的搞黄视频| 亚洲国产精品成人久久小说| 99re6热这里在线精品视频| 欧美bdsm另类| 我要看黄色一级片免费的| 97超碰精品成人国产| 美女国产视频在线观看| 五月天丁香电影| 国产成人午夜福利电影在线观看| 亚洲av中文av极速乱| 一二三四中文在线观看免费高清| 久久久国产欧美日韩av| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠久久av| 校园人妻丝袜中文字幕| 亚洲图色成人| 国产免费福利视频在线观看| 国产综合精华液| 亚洲国产精品国产精品| 久久久午夜欧美精品| 久久国产亚洲av麻豆专区| 自线自在国产av| 伊人亚洲综合成人网| 99九九在线精品视频| 国产精品国产av在线观看| 国产一区二区在线观看av| 天堂俺去俺来也www色官网| 精品熟女少妇av免费看| 久久人人爽av亚洲精品天堂| 在线观看一区二区三区激情| 在线观看免费日韩欧美大片 | 欧美人与善性xxx| 搡女人真爽免费视频火全软件| 亚洲精品日本国产第一区| 日本黄色日本黄色录像| 精品午夜福利在线看| 啦啦啦啦在线视频资源| 成人亚洲欧美一区二区av| 搡老乐熟女国产| 国产亚洲av片在线观看秒播厂| 国产黄色免费在线视频| 免费观看无遮挡的男女| h视频一区二区三区| 亚洲国产av影院在线观看| 丝袜脚勾引网站| 国产av码专区亚洲av| 91在线精品国自产拍蜜月| 天天影视国产精品| 精品国产乱码久久久久久小说| 午夜老司机福利剧场| 成年女人在线观看亚洲视频| 精品久久久久久久久亚洲| 51国产日韩欧美| 国产精品.久久久| 久久ye,这里只有精品| av在线老鸭窝| 亚洲精品日韩av片在线观看| 亚洲成人手机| 在线精品无人区一区二区三| 多毛熟女@视频| 精品亚洲成国产av| 国产一区二区三区av在线| 中文乱码字字幕精品一区二区三区| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜添av毛片| 在线看a的网站| 久久影院123| 亚洲国产成人一精品久久久| 成年人免费黄色播放视频| freevideosex欧美| 久久久久久伊人网av| 免费不卡的大黄色大毛片视频在线观看| 亚洲av国产av综合av卡| 一区在线观看完整版| 桃花免费在线播放| 欧美少妇被猛烈插入视频| 国产亚洲一区二区精品| 老司机影院毛片| 国产日韩一区二区三区精品不卡 | 国产欧美亚洲国产| 亚洲欧洲精品一区二区精品久久久 | 午夜激情福利司机影院| 国产成人精品一,二区| 最新中文字幕久久久久| 亚洲av免费高清在线观看| 99国产精品免费福利视频| 国产欧美另类精品又又久久亚洲欧美| 久久久精品区二区三区| 纵有疾风起免费观看全集完整版| 亚洲,一卡二卡三卡| 97超碰精品成人国产| 欧美精品国产亚洲| 18禁动态无遮挡网站| 久久久午夜欧美精品| 18禁在线无遮挡免费观看视频| 午夜影院在线不卡| 亚洲欧美成人综合另类久久久| 少妇 在线观看| 精品国产露脸久久av麻豆| av国产精品久久久久影院| av专区在线播放| 亚洲av男天堂| 18禁观看日本| 成人手机av| 国产黄色视频一区二区在线观看| 国产精品.久久久| a级毛片免费高清观看在线播放| 伊人久久国产一区二区| 亚洲天堂av无毛| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区| 插逼视频在线观看| 国产免费一区二区三区四区乱码| 黄色欧美视频在线观看| 国产 一区精品| 亚洲欧美中文字幕日韩二区| 夫妻性生交免费视频一级片| 午夜免费鲁丝| 亚洲人成网站在线观看播放| 国产亚洲欧美精品永久| 成年av动漫网址| 亚洲熟女精品中文字幕| 欧美3d第一页| 男女边摸边吃奶| 亚洲av免费高清在线观看| 国产成人精品福利久久| 久久青草综合色| 日日摸夜夜添夜夜添av毛片| 一级a做视频免费观看| 国产日韩欧美在线精品| 亚洲av.av天堂| 亚洲国产成人一精品久久久| 2022亚洲国产成人精品| 亚洲欧美一区二区三区国产| 夫妻性生交免费视频一级片| 中文字幕av电影在线播放| 人妻制服诱惑在线中文字幕| 精品久久久久久久久av| 99热这里只有精品一区| 久久免费观看电影| 水蜜桃什么品种好| 久久人妻熟女aⅴ| av天堂久久9| 97在线人人人人妻| 99热国产这里只有精品6| 亚洲av综合色区一区| 18在线观看网站| 国产免费一区二区三区四区乱码| 国产在线一区二区三区精| 3wmmmm亚洲av在线观看| 一本久久精品| 久久毛片免费看一区二区三区| 中国三级夫妇交换| av黄色大香蕉| 最黄视频免费看| 狠狠精品人妻久久久久久综合| 91国产中文字幕| 99热这里只有是精品在线观看| 欧美精品人与动牲交sv欧美| 亚洲欧美中文字幕日韩二区| 寂寞人妻少妇视频99o| 最近手机中文字幕大全| 人人妻人人澡人人爽人人夜夜| 在线观看美女被高潮喷水网站| 两个人免费观看高清视频| 在线观看三级黄色| 日本欧美视频一区| xxx大片免费视频| 精品久久久噜噜| 亚洲国产av影院在线观看| 三上悠亚av全集在线观看| 成人国产麻豆网| 久久久久久久大尺度免费视频| 久久性视频一级片| 精品国产超薄肉色丝袜足j| 成年人黄色毛片网站| 老汉色∧v一级毛片| 国产精品偷伦视频观看了| 黄色视频在线播放观看不卡| 免费观看av网站的网址| 欧美日韩国产mv在线观看视频| 国产三级黄色录像| 午夜福利视频精品| 久久av网站| 成人三级做爰电影| 精品一区二区三卡| 在线av久久热| tube8黄色片| 亚洲国产av新网站| 丝瓜视频免费看黄片| 免费观看a级毛片全部| 在线亚洲精品国产二区图片欧美| 嫁个100分男人电影在线观看| 亚洲欧美精品综合一区二区三区| 亚洲七黄色美女视频| 曰老女人黄片| 麻豆av在线久日| 国产视频一区二区在线看| 欧美乱妇无乱码| 久久久久久免费高清国产稀缺| 久久天躁狠狠躁夜夜2o2o| 日韩一区二区三区影片| 青草久久国产| 免费在线观看影片大全网站| bbb黄色大片| 十八禁高潮呻吟视频| 在线av久久热| 精品国产一区二区三区四区第35| 精品欧美一区二区三区在线| 在线观看一区二区三区激情| 国产区一区二久久| 亚洲少妇的诱惑av| 国产成人免费观看mmmm| 十八禁高潮呻吟视频| 一本—道久久a久久精品蜜桃钙片| 亚洲伊人色综图| 亚洲成a人片在线一区二区| tube8黄色片| 成人国语在线视频| 久久精品熟女亚洲av麻豆精品| 亚洲第一欧美日韩一区二区三区 | 国内毛片毛片毛片毛片毛片| 国产在视频线精品| 国产av精品麻豆| 无限看片的www在线观看| 交换朋友夫妻互换小说| 欧美日韩精品网址| 免费人妻精品一区二区三区视频| 亚洲成人免费电影在线观看| 免费观看a级毛片全部| 黑人巨大精品欧美一区二区蜜桃| 精品熟女少妇八av免费久了| 99国产极品粉嫩在线观看| 欧美一级毛片孕妇| 久久精品国产亚洲av香蕉五月 | √禁漫天堂资源中文www| 在线永久观看黄色视频| 久久影院123| 99国产精品免费福利视频| 一级毛片女人18水好多| 视频区欧美日本亚洲| 亚洲午夜理论影院| 日韩欧美免费精品| 国产精品免费视频内射| a在线观看视频网站| 亚洲国产欧美日韩在线播放| 热99re8久久精品国产| 新久久久久国产一级毛片| 最新在线观看一区二区三区| 精品一品国产午夜福利视频| 丰满人妻熟妇乱又伦精品不卡| 考比视频在线观看| 人人妻人人添人人爽欧美一区卜|