• <tr id="yyy80"></tr>
  • <sup id="yyy80"></sup>
  • <tfoot id="yyy80"><noscript id="yyy80"></noscript></tfoot>
  • 99热精品在线国产_美女午夜性视频免费_国产精品国产高清国产av_av欧美777_自拍偷自拍亚洲精品老妇_亚洲熟女精品中文字幕_www日本黄色视频网_国产精品野战在线观看 ?

    Context and Content: From Language to Thought

    2011-12-05 06:39:48FRANOISRECANATI
    當(dāng)代外語研究 2011年12期

    FRAN?OIS RECANATI

    (Institut Jean-Nicod, France)

    1.SPEECH ACT THEORY

    I was raised as a continental philosopher (in Paris, in the seventies).Initially a disciple of Lacan, I discovered analytic philosophy by chance.I had noticed similarities between Lacan’s approach to natural language and (what I knew of) ordinary language philosophy as practiced in Oxford in mid-twentieth century.Like Lacan, ordinary language philosophers criticized the attempt to understand natural language by studying the constructed languages of logic.So I started investigating ordinary language philosophy to see how much could be extracted from it in the service of a broadly Lacanian conception.It took me little time to realize that the analytic way of doing philosophy, with its characteristic clarity and simplicity, was more to my taste than the obscurity and pomposity which plagued continental philosophy in general, and Lacanian theorizing in particular.I myself became an analytic philosopher, and started interacting with philosophers in the UK and the US, while doing my best, with a few enlightened colleagues from various European countries, to develop that sort of philosophy on the continent.

    Ordinary language philosophers thought important features of natural language were not revealed, but hidden, by the logical approach initiated by Frege, Russell and the logical positivists.They advocated a more descriptive approach and emphasized the ‘pragmatic’ dimension of language.Language isused, and language use, or the activity of speech, deserves to be studied in its own right.Moroever, its study is likely to shed light on linguistic forms and their meaning, which meaning is indissociable from the way the expressions are used.Ordinary language philosophy thus initated a ‘pragmatic turn’ in the philosophy of language and contributed to the development of a new linguistic discipline: the so-called pragmatics.The fact that my entry point into analytic philosophy was via ordinary language philosophy explains why my initial contributions to the philosophy of language were in that area.

    Speech act theory (Austin 1975; Searle 1969) is the core of pragmatics and I started my new career as a speech act theorist.Speech act theory is concerned with communication—not communication in the narrow sense of transmission of information, but communication in a broader sense which includes the issuing of orders, the asking of questions, the making of apologies and promises, etc.According to the theory, a speech act is more than merely the utterance of a grammatical sentence endowed with sense and reference.To speak is also todosomething in a fairly strong sense—it is to perform what Austin called an ‘illocutionary act’.

    Illocutionary acts are generally introduced ostensively, by examples—as I did above; and they are distinguished both from the act of merely saying something (‘locutionary’ act) and from the act of causing something to happen by saying something (‘perlocutionary’ act, e.g.frightening, convincing, etc.).The nature of the intermediate category of ‘illocutionary acts’ remains unclear, however.The pioneers of speech act theory, Austin and Searle, advocated an institutional or conventional approach.Like Malinowski, one of the early advocates of the pragmatic turn in the study of language,[注]See Malinowski 1923.they used to insist on thesocialdimension of language as opposed to its cognitive or representational function.In their framework the illocutionary acts performed in speech, like the acts that are performed in games (e.g.‘winning a set’ in tennis), are governed by rules, and exist only against a background of social conventions.As pragmatics developed, however, it is thepsychologicaldimension of language use that came to the forefront of discussions, in part as a result of Grice’s work on meaning and communication.

    In his famous 1957 article “Meaning”, Grice defined a pragmatic notion of meaning: the notion ofsomeone’smeaning something by a piece of behaviour (a gesture, an utterance, or whatnot).Grice’s idea was that this pragmatic notion of meaning could be used to analyse the semantic notion, i.e.what it is for a linguisticexpressionto have meaning.Strawson soon pointed out that Grice’s pragmatic notion of meaning could also be used to characterize the elusive notion of an illocutionary act (Strawson 1964).The view that illocutionary acts are essentially conventional acts (like the acts which owe their existence to the rules of a particular game) was dominant in speech act theory until Strawson established a bridge between Grice’s theory of meaning and Austin’s theory of illocutionary acts.The alternative, Gricean approach advocated by Strawson marked a ‘cognitive turn’ within pragmatics.The crucial notion became that of an audience-directed intention and the crucial mechanism through which one is able to read someone else’s mind and decipher his or her intentions.It is to the development of the new framework that—along with others like Bach and Harnish (1979) and Sperber and Wilson (1986)—I contributed in my early publications, especially the bookMeaningandForce(1987—originally published in French asLesEnoncésperformatifs, 1981).

    I said above that a perlocutionary act consists in bringing about certain effects by an utterance.For example, by saying to you“It is raining”, I bring it about that you believe that it is raining.Now, according to the Grice-Strawson analysis, to perform theillocutionaryact of asserting that it is raining is (in part) to make manifest to the addressee one’s intention to bring it about, by this utterance, that the addressee believes that it is raining.(This is not the full story, of course.) An illocutionary act, therefore, involves the manifestation of a corresponding perlocutionary intention.But there is a special twist which the suggested analysis inherits from Grice’s original conception of meaning: the intention must be made manifest in a specially ‘overt’ manner.Not only must the speaker’s intention to bring about a certain belief in the addressee be revealed by his utterance, but his intention to reveal it must also be revealed, and it must be revealed in the same overt manner.This characteristic (if puzzling) feature of overtness is often captured by considering the revealed intention itself asreflexive: A communicative intention, i.e.the type of intention whose manifestation (and recognition) constitutes the performance of an illocutionary act, is the intention to produce a certain perlocutionary effect (e.g.bringing about a certain belief in the addressee) via the addressee’s recognition ofthisintention.

    In my bookMeaningandForceI offered a systematic critique of the conventionalist picture and an elaboration of the alternative framework.The cornerstone of the conventionalist approach defended by Austin and Searle was the notion of a ‘performative formula’.Austin had noticed that one can perform an illocutionary actVby saying that oneV’s.One can promise by saying “I promise” or one can order by saying “I order”.The performative formula, e.g.“I promise”, is for Austin and Searle a form of words which, by convention, enables the speaker to perform the act which it names (here the act of promising).It is, moreover, constitutive of the acts in question that there are formulas which by convention serve to perform them.I criticized that view and tried to show that, within an appropriate version of the Gricean framework, one can account for performative utterances without departing from standard principles of compositional semantics.While Austin and Searle treated the ‘performative formula’ as endowed with certain powers in virtue of brute conventions, I argued that their efficacy is best explained by appealing to the nature of communicative acts.If to communicate something is to make manifest one’s intention to do so, then it is unsurprising that one can perform a communicative act by declaring that one does.

    2.THE PRAGMATICS OF WHAT IS SAID

    In the new framework, an utterance is seen as a meaningful action, i.e.an action which provides interpreters with evidence concerning the agent’s intentions.What distinguishes communicative acts from other meaningful actions is what can be inferred from the evidence: A communicative act is an act which provides evidence of a certaincommunicativeintentionon the part of the speaker.In other words, the speaker’s intention to communicate something is what explains his utterance, considered as a piece of behaviour.From this point of view, the content of the communicative act—whatis communicated—is the total content of the communicative intentions which can be inferred from it.Let us call this the utterance’s communicative meaning, distinct from the literal or conventional meaning of the sentence (determined by the grammar).Understanding isessentiallyan inferential process in this framework, and the conventional meaning of the sentence provides only part of the evidence used in determining the communicative meaning of the utterance.

    On this picture, communication does not essentially rely on the coding of information.Communication is possible even if one does not share a language.Even without a common language, one can manage to let the hearer recognize one’s communicative intentions.And when the communicators do share a language, what they communicate using that language typically goes well beyond what they literally encode in their words.

    Grice’s theory of conversational implicatures—a particular application of his general theory of meaning—shows how one can communicate something implicitly (Grice 1989).On Grice’s account, implicatures are derived through an inference which enables the interpreter to grasp the speaker’s communicative intention despite the fact that it is not articulated in words.The inference makes use of two crucial premises (in addition to background knowledge): (1) the fact that the speaker has said what she has said, and (2) the fact that the speaker, qua communicator, obeys (or is supposed to obey) the rules of communication or, as Grice puts it, the ‘maxims of conversation.’ Conversational implicatures are only a special case, however.Because of the role played by the first premise in the inference through which they are derived, conversational implicatures belong to the ‘post-semantic’ layer of interpretation.This means that, in order to derive the implicatures of an utterance, an interpreter must start by identifying what the speaker literally says (the utterance’s ‘semantic content’).But pragmatic inference isalsorequired to identify what is said—or so I have argued since the early eighties.

    In“The Pragmatics of What is Said”(1989) and subsequent work, I drew a distinction between primary and secondary pragmatic processes.Secondary pragmatic processes are those which presuppose the prior identification of what is said (as in Grice’s picture), while primary pragmatic processes are those that are involved in the determination of what is said.Shortly afterwards, in the second part of my 1993 bookDirectReference(a second part entitled “Truth-Conditional Pragmatics”, like the book I published in 2010), I drew a further distinction between two types of primary pragmatic processes: saturation and modulation.

    Saturation is a pragmatic process triggered by something in the sentence itself—some linguistic expression which introduces a slot to be contextually filled or (equivalently) a free variable to which a value must be contextually assigned.To compute the proposition expressed by an utterance, it is necessary to assign contextual values to indexicals, (unbound) pronouns etc.For example, if the speaker uses a demonstrative pronoun and says “She is cute,” the hearer must determine who the speaker means by “she”in order to fix the utterance’s truth-conditional content.Likewise, if I say “John is ready”but the context does not provide an answer to the question:“ready for what?”, I have not said anything definite; I haven not expressed a complete proposition.Saturation, so understood, ismandatory: No proposition is expressed unless a value is assigned to the variable.A ‘slot’ has to be contextually filled, which leaves the utterance semantically incomplete in case it remains unfilled.

    With modulation, the situation is quite different.What modulation does is tomodifywhatever content the expression literally possesses (e.g.by making it more specific, as in free enrichment, or less specific, as in sense extension).Since the expression at issue already possesses a determinate content, modulation is not a mandatory process, as far as semantic interpretation is concerned.It is optional and takes place only to make sense of what the speaker is saying.In other words what triggers the contextual process of modulation is not a property of the linguistic material, but a property of the context of utterance.The meaning of words is adjusted through some kind ofpragmaticcoercion.As I put it in my bookLiteralMeaning, in which I summarize that line of research.

    Sense modulation is essential to speech, because we use a (more or less) fixed stock of lexemes to talk about an indefinite variety of things, situations and experiences.Through the interaction between the context-independent meanings of our words and the particulars of the situation talked about, contextualised, modulated senses emerge, appropriate to the situation at hand.(Recanati 2004: 131)

    The emphasis on the role of pragmatic factors in the determination of what is said led me to revive the literalism/contextualism debate which had marked the middle of the twentieth century.According to the family of views I call ‘literalism’, the proposition expressed by an utterance is, by and large, fixed by the conventions of the language.According to contextualism, the alternative position reminiscent of ordinary language philosophy which I set out to defend inLiteralMeaning, an utterance expresses a fully determinate, truth-evaluable proposition only in the context of a speech act.The rules of the language by themselves are not sufficient to endow a sentence with truth-conditional content.

    To be sure, everybody accepts that sentences containing indexicals express a proposition only with respect to context.This, however, was not considered as a major threat to the literalist picture for two reasons.First, saturation itselfisgoverned by the conventions of the language.The meaning of an indexical is, or includes, atoken-reflexiverulewhich tells us how, for each particular token of the expression, we can determine the content carried by that token as a function of the circumstances of utterance.(Thus the meaning of ‘I’ is the rule that a token of that word refers to the producer of that token, the meaning of ‘today’ is the rule that a token of that word refers to the day on which the token is produced, the meaning of ‘we’ is a rule that a token of that word refers to a group that contains the speaker, and so on and so forth.) Second, even if indexicality speaks against literalism, it is a quite restricted phenomenon: There are only a limited number of expressions that require contextual saturation, so the contextualist attack remains under control.In response, I pointed out that many expressions in need of contextual saturation are semantically under-specified rather than indexical in the narrow sense.Their content depends upon the context, but they are not ‘token-reflexive’.A good example of under-specification is the genitive construction, as in ‘John’s car’: this phrase refers to a car bearing a certain relationRto John, which relation is determined in context, without being linguistically specified.(It may be the car John bought, or the car he dreamt of last night, or anything.) The linguistic meaning of the construction does not encode a token-reflexive rule telling us how, for each particular token of the expression, we can determine the content carried by that token as a function of the circumstances of utterance.So it is not true that saturation is ‘governed by the conventions of the language’, in such a way that pragmatic inference might be dispensed with.As for the second tenet of the literalist defense—the fact that context-sensivity is a limited phenomenon corresponding to a particular class of expressions—it collapses as soon as one accepts pragmatic modulation as a possible determinant of truth-conditional content.For modulation itself is context-sensitive:Whetherornotmodulation comes into play, and if it does,whichmodulation operation takes place, is a matter of context.It follows that what an expression actually contributes to the thought expressed by the utterance in which it occurs isalwaysa matter of context.

    Many people attacked contextualism on the grounds that it is incompatible with the project of constructing a systematic semantics for natural language—a project that has been remarkably successful thanks to the progress of formal semantics over the past thirty years.In my 2010 book,Truth-ConditionalPragmatics, I attempt to defend contextualism against this charge by showing there is no straightforward incompatibility between context-sensitivity and systematicity, and by sketching what a compositional pragmatics might be like.

    3.SITUATIONS

    Saturation and modulation are two families of pragmatic processes that are ‘primary’ in the sense that they affect what is said—the utterance’s intuitive truth-conditional content.Because of the role they play, the same sentence-type may be used to express different propositions in different contexts.But a proposition determines a truth-value only with respect to a ‘circumstance of evaluation’ (for example a world, or a world and a time, or a situation, depending on one’s semantic framework); and the circumstance with respect to which a given content is to be evaluated itself depends upon the context in which that content is expressed.This gives rise to a third type of context-sensitivity, to which I have devoted a number of studies since the mid-nineties (including a large part of my booksOratioObliqua,OratioRecta, 2000, andPerspectivalThought, 2007).

    Consider the following example, from Barwise and Etchemendy (1987: 29).Commenting upon a poker game I am watching, I say:“Claire has a good hand.” What I say is true just in case Claire has a good hand at the moment of utterance.But suppose I made a mistake and Claire is not among the players in that game.Suppose further that, by coincidence, she happens to be playing bridge in some other part of town and has a good hand there.The proposition I express is the proposition that Claire has a good hand, andthatis true; still, intuitively, my utterance isnottrue, because the situation it is about (the poker game I am watching) is not one in which Claire has a good hand at the time of utterance.The utterance concerns a particular situation (the poker game I am watching) and the proposition it expresses is not truewithrespecttothatsituation.This arguably shows that an utterance’s intuitive truth-value depends upon two things: its semantic content, and the situation with respect to which that content is evaluated.The utterance is true iff the proposition it expresses is true with respect to the situation it concerns.Which situation that is is determined by the context, the interests of the speech participants, what they are talking about, etc.It corresponds to the ‘topic’ of the utterance in the traditional sense: That which the speaker is talking about.

    The contextual determination of the relevant situation is neither saturation nor modulation.It is not saturation because there is no indexical or pronominal expression standing for the situation talked about.The situation talked about is not, or at least need not be, represented in the content of what we say.Rather, what we say—the semantic content of our utterance—is evaluated with respect to a contextually provided situation, which remains external to that content.Nor is the contextual provision of the situation talked about a matter of modulation.What undergoes contextual modulation is always the meaning of a particular expression in the sentence, and here it is the content of the whole sentence which is globally taken to concern a particular situation.

    The distinction between ‘content’ and ‘circumstance of evaluation’ is old in the philosophy of language (see in particular Kaplan 1989; Lewis 1980).In modal logic, propositions are evaluated relative to possible worlds.A proposition may be true relative to a world w, and false relative to another world w’.A proposition whose truth-value varies across worlds is said to becontingent(as opposed tonecessary).Similarly, in tense logic, propositions are evaluated relative to times.A proposition (e.g.the proposition that Socrates is sitting) may be true relative to a time t, and false relative to another time t’.A proposition that has this property is said to betemporal(as opposed toeternal).For various purposes, the circumstance of evaluation has been enriched with even more ‘coordinates’ than a world and a time.In his work on ‘a(chǎn)ttitudesdese’, David Lewis has suggested that the circumstance of evaluation should include an individual in addition to a time and a world, in order to capture the egocentric perspective of the subject of thought (Lewis 1979).Similarly, it has been proposed that the circumstance of evaluation should include normative standards (e.g.standards of taste) to account for evaluative propositions such as the proposition that spinach is delicious.(According to the ‘semantic relativists’, that proposition is true relative to some standards of taste, and false relative to others.See K?lbel and Carpintero 2008 for a survey.)

    On the canonical picture of content we inherited from Frege, these ‘relativized propositions’ (temporal propositions, evaluative propositions, etc.) are not genuine propositions.Genuine propositions are supposed to be true or false.But the proposition that Socrates is sitting (or the proposition that spinach is delicious) is not evaluable as true or false, or at least, it is not evaluableunlesswe are given a further ingredient—a particular time, or a particular standard of taste, relative to which the content can be evaluated.Let us focus on the temporal example to make the general point.In the absence of a time specification, the ‘proposition’ that Socrates is sitting is only ‘true-at’ certain times and ‘false-at’ others.It is not true or false absolutely.It is, therefore, not a genuine proposition (thought) by Frege’s lights:

    A thought is not true at one time and false at another, but it is either true or false, tertium non datur.The false appearance that a thought can be true at one time and false at another arises from an incomplete expression.A complete proposition or expression of a thought must also contain a time datum.(Frege 1967: 338, cited in Evans 1985: 350)

    As Evans points out, the problem of incompleteness does not arise in the modal case.Even if a thought is said to be ‘true-at’ one world and ‘false-at’ another, as in modal logic, this does not prevent it from being true (or false)toutcourt.It is truetoutcourtiff it is true-at the actual world.But the ‘thought’ that Socrates is sitting cannot be evaluated as true or falsetoutcourt.In the absence of a contextually supplied time it canonlybe ascribed relative, ‘truth-at’-conditions.Only a particular, dated utterance of such a sentence can be endowed with genuine truth-conditions.What this shows, according to Frege, is that the time of utterance is a constitutive part of the ‘hybrid symbol’ of which the sentence uttered at that time is another part.What expresses a complete content (a genuine proposition) is not the sentence “Socrates is sitting”by itself, but the hybrid symbol, that is, the sentence in conjunction with a particular time of utterance.

    Let us grant Frege that the complete content of the utterance “Socrates is sitting” involves more than the ‘temporal proposition’ expressed by the sentence (a proposition that can only be evaluated relative to particular times, but not absolutely); it additionally involves the time of utterance, which is tacitly referred to.This is compatible with the content/circumstance distinction, provided we draw a further distinction between two notions of content—explicit content and complete content.In our example, the time of utterance, which features in the circumstance of evaluation, is constitutive of thecompletecontent of the utterance, but it remains external to the ‘explicit’ content of the utterance, that is, the content expressed by the sentence itself.In this framework, the complete content of an utterance consists of two things: the explicit content, and the circumstance with respect to which we evaluate that content.Once it is admitted that we need these two components, we can tolerate explicit contents that are not semantically complete in Frege’s sense, i.e.endowed with absolute truth-conditions.We can, because the circumstance is there which enables the content to be suitably completed.Thus the content of tensed sentences is semantically incomplete, yet the circumstance (the time) relative to which such a sentence is evaluated is sufficient to complete it.The same thing holds for evaluative propositions, or for Lewis’sdesecontents.

    In the Barwise-Etchemendy example, the explicit content is the proposition that Claire has a good hand.This is evaluated with respect to a circumstance involving not only a particular time (the time of utterance) but also a particular situation at that time: The poker game the speaker and his addressee are watching.The two levels of content enable us to account for our conflicting intuitions: what the speaker says (viz., that Claire has a good hand) is true, since Claire happens to have a good hand where she is; yet the utterance as a whole isnottrue, because the situation it is about (the poker game the speaker is watching) is not one in which Claire has a good hand.

    On this picture, the context plays two roles: Through saturation and modulation, it contributes to determining the proposition expressed by the uttered sentence—its explicit content; but it also determines the circumstance with respect to which that content is to be evaluated.Like modulation and unlike indexicality, this third form of context-dependence, which we may call ‘circumstance-relativity’, is not tied to a particular class of expressions; it is ageneralfeature of language use.It is, therefore, relevant to one of the main questions at issue in the literalism/contextualism debate: How generalized is context-dependence? My claim is that,wheneverwe say something, what we say concerns a particular situation that we are attempting to characterize, and which the context indicates.The utterance is true if the situation corresponds to the way we characterize it.That means that the same content may be evaluated as true or false depending on the situation we take to be contextually relevant for its evaluation.This, again, is a general feature which applies to every utterance, whether or not it involves indexicals or other expressions in need of contextual saturation.

    4.FROM LANGUAGE TO THOUGHT

    The subtitle of my bookDirectReferenceis: “From language to thought”.One of my central concerns over the past fifteen years has been to extend to representation in general, and to mental representation in particular, some of the lessons we learn from the study of linguistic representations.

    When we move from language to thought, the role of context seems to be more widely accepted, as if ‘literalism’ was out of place in this area.The majority view has it that no content is wholly independent of context: The content of mental representations essentially depends upon the environment.Thus ‘externalism’ is the dominant position in the philosophy of mind, while contextualism remains a minority position in the philosophy of language.

    Yet the contrast should not be overestimated.The sort of context-dependence that externalism generalizes is rather trivial.It is the content of mental representation-typesthat is said to depend upon the environment—e.g.the environment in which the species has evolved, or the environment in which the concepts whose content is at issue have been acquired.As I wrote inDirectReference,

    Mental contents are (...) environment-dependent in the sense that the existence of a certain type of content depends on there being systematic causal relations between states of the mind/brain and types of objects in the external world.Thus a (type of) configuration in the brain is a concept of water only if it is normally tokened in the presence of water.It follows that there would be no water-concept if there were no water.This sort of environment-dependence is what Externalism is concerned with.It affects mental states considered as types: The content of a mental statetypedepends on the environment—namely, on what normally causes a tokening of the type.(Recanati 1993: 214-15)

    It is quite obvious that the same ‘syntactic’ configuration in the brain would have a different content, or no content at all, if it was found elsewhere than in the brain of organisms with a certain habitat and a certain history of living in that habitat.The form of context-dependence that externalism generalizes is comparable to a trivial form of context-dependence which can be found on the language side and which Bar-Hillel talks about in the following passage:

    Let me (...) mention a brand of dependency which embraces even the non-indexical sentences.I mean the fact that any token has to be understood to belong to a certain language.When somebody hears somebody else utter a sound which sounds to him like the English ‘nine’, he might sometimes have good reasons to believe that this sound does not refer to the number nine, and this in the case that he will have good reasons to assume that this sound belongs to the German language, in which case it refers to the same as the English ‘no’.In this sense, no linguistic expression is completely independent of the pragmatic context.But just because this kind of dependence is universal, it is trivial, and we shall forget it for our purposes.(Bar-Hillel 1954/1970: 80)

    Being comparable to the trivial generalization of context-dependence Bar-Hillel talks about, the generalization of context-dependence advocated by externalism is quite different from that advocated by contextualism in the language case.This raises the following question: Are there, in the mental realm, forms of context-dependence that are similar to the forms of context-dependence at issue in the literalism/contextualism debate?

    In the same passage fromDirectReferencewhich I quoted above, I mention

    another form of environment-dependence which affectstokensrather than types.The ‘wide’ content of a particular token of the thought “This man looks happy” is environment-dependent in the (stronger) sense that it depends on the context of occurrence of this token: It depends on the particular man who happens to causethistokeningof the thought.(Recanati 1993: 214-15)

    Insofar as it affects the content carried by a particular token, rather than the constant meaning of the type, this form of context-dependence is similar to the dependence of the content of an indexical sentence upon the context of utterance.Indeed the dependence of the ‘wide’ content of a thought upon the context of thinking is sometimes referred to as ‘mental indexicality’; a label that is motivated, in part, by the fact that the thoughts whose content is dependent upon the context in this way are typically expressed by indexical sentences such as “This man looks happy” or “I am hot”.

    Thanks to the work of Perry and others, it is generally acknowledged that there are thoughts whose truth-conditional content depends upon the context, just as there are sentences whose truth-conditional content depends upon the context.What remains controversial, however, is the idea that the thoughts whose truth-conditional content depends upon the context are like mental sentences that contain indexical vocabulary items (concepts) whose function is similar to that of indexical words.On this view, there is a ‘concept of self’ that is the mental counterpart of the word ‘I’.When Castor and Pollux both think “I am hot”, they entertain distinct thoughts by Frege’s lights, since the truth-conditions of the thoughts differ (one is true just in case Castor is hot, the other just in case Pollux is hot).Different though they are, the two thoughts share the same vehicle, and that is where we find the concept of self.Both Castor’s thought and Pollux’s thought involve that concept construed as the mental vehicle through which one refers to oneself.Just as the word ‘I’ refers to distinct individuals and therefore acquires a different sense (content) in different contexts, the mental ‘I’ also refers to distinct individuals and acquires a different content in different contexts.

    This view has been elaborated by John Perry, among others (Perry 1993).Perry uses Kaplan’s content/character distinction and applies it to the analysis of thought.The thought-vehicle is a mental state whose constant meaning or ‘role’ is or determines a function from contexts to contents.In context the vehicle carries a content that is what the subject assents to or dissents from.But the subject’s assent or dissent depends upon the vehicle.One may assent to a certain content when that content is carried by a certain vehicle (e.g.‘I am French’) and not when it is carried by a distinct vehicle (‘Recanati is French’).Same content, different vehicles, different behaviours.In the other direction, the fact that Castor and Pollux use the same vehicle—are in the same state—is indicated by their common behaviour: When they think “I am hot”, they both take off their sweater or open the window, or do something like that.Different contents, same vehicle, same (type of) behaviour.(See Perry 1977)

    That is not the only possible way of dealing with mental indexicality, however.Another way of dealing with it, advocated by David Lewis (1979), appeals to what I called ‘circumstance-relativity’.Circumstance-relativity yields truth-conditional differences that cannot be traced to the representational vehicle.The same sentence “It is raining” expresses different propositions in different contexts not because it is ambiguous or involves hidden indexicals, but because the (explicit) content that is expressed by that sentence is evaluated with respect to varying circumstances.What is contextually variable, in this sort of case, is the circumstance, not the content we evaluate; but the complete truth-conditional content of the utterance involves the circumstance as well as the explicit content: The utterance is true iff its (explicit) content is true with respect to the relevant circumstance.If we change the circumstance of evaluation, we change the overall truth-conditions.

    According to David Lewis, thoughts that we would express by using indexical sentences are actually best handled in terms of circumstance-relativity.For Lewis, there is a thought content (not merely a ‘vehicle’) which Castor and Pollux share when they both think “I am hot”; but that content is not a classical proposition.Rather than a classical proposition, true at some worlds and false at others, the common content of their respective thoughts isthepropertyofbeinghot, which Castor and Pollux each self-ascribes.Rather than draw a distinction between the vehicle (or character) and the content of their beliefs, as Perry does, Lewis thinks we need to relativize the truth of what they think to the right sort of circumstance.In the case of belief and other attitudes, the circumstance of evaluation isaworldcenteredonthebelieveratthetimeofbelief, and the explicit content of the attitudes, to be evaluated with respect to the believer’s centered world, is a property rather than a classical proposition.To believe something is, for Lewis, always to self-ascribe a property, e.g.the property of being hot, or the property of living in a world in which Frege died in 1925.In this framework indexical belief falls out as a particular case.

    In my own work, I have pursued both directions of research and tried to integrate them within a unified picture.InPerspectivalThought, following Lewis, I appeal to circumstance-relativity to model the egocentric content of experiential states.But I don’t think we have to give up the standard treatment of mental indexicals à la Perry.InDirectReferenceand in a forthcoming book,MentalFiles, I try to give substance to the idea that we refer to objects through mental files which themselves work like indexicals.On the general picture I advocate, there is both mental indexicalityandcircumstance-relativity.

    5.MENTAL FILES

    Imagine a subject who entertains the thought “This man looks happy” while having a certain visual experience.Let’s suppose the man he perceives is Bob.Since Bob is mentally referred to, the thought’s truth will arguably depend upon Bob’s properties: It will depend upon whether Bob (is a man and) looks happy.Had the context been different, the man whom the subject perceives would have been someone else—say Bill.Then Bill would have been referred to, and the thought’s truth-conditions would involve Bill.That is so even if we suppose that no qualitative change occurs in the subject’s visual experience from one context to the next: The thought that is expressed changes purely as a result of an external change in the context.One thought is true iff Bob (is a man and) looks happy, the other is true if and only if Bill (is a man and) looks happy.Since one thought could be true and the other false, this is sufficient to show that the two thoughts are distinct, by Fregean standards.(For Frege, two thoughts are distinct if they can take different truth-values.) In the vehicle sense, however, the thoughts are arguably the same: internally, the subject’s state of mind is the same.In both cases he thinks “This man looks happy” while having a visual experience that is qualitatively identical in the two cases.This is similar to the subject’ssaying“This man looks happy” twice and thereby expressing distinct Fregean thoughts simply because the context, hence the referent of the demonstrative, has changed from one occurrence to the next.

    In a series of studies I tried to account for indexical reference in thought in terms ofmentalfiles.Mental files are based on contextual relations to objects in the environment; different types of files correspond to different types of relation.The characteristic feature of the relations on which mental files are based is that they areepistemicallyrewarding(hence my name for them: ER relations).They enable the subject to gain information from the objects to which he stands in these relations.The role of the file is to store information about these objects—information that is made available through the relations in question.So mental files are ‘a(chǎn)bout objects’: Like singular terms in the language, they refer, or are supposed to refer.They are, indeed, the mental counterparts of singular terms.What they refer to is not determined by properties which the subject takes the referent to have (i.e.by information—or misinformation—inthe file), but in externalist fashion, through the subject’s ER relations to various entities in the environment in which the file fulfills its function.The information (or misinformation) in the file therefore corresponds to the properties which the subject takes the referent to have, but these properties are not what determines the reference of the file.What determines the reference of the file is the ER relation on which the file is based.

    In the above example (“This man looks happy”) the relevant mental file is a demonstrative file based on a perceptual/attentional relation to the object of thought.This is a temporary file that exists only as long as the subject is able to focus his or her attention on the object given in perception.In general, the contextual relations to objects which indexical reference exploits are short-term relations to the referent.Thus typical indexical concepts like HERE or NOW are temporary mental files based on short-lived ER relations to the place we are in, or to the current time, which relations enable the subject to know (by using his senses) what is going on at the place or time in question.There are exceptions, though.According to Perry (2002), the SELF file is astablefile based upon a special relation which every individual permanently bears to himself or herself, namely identity.In virtue ofbeinga certain individual, I am in a position to gain information concerning that individual in all sorts of ways in which I can gain information about no one else, e.g.through proprioception and kinaesthesis.The mental file SELF serves as a repository for information gained in this way.[注]As we shall see in due course, this is not the only sort of information about oneself that can go into the file.A file based on a certain ER relation contains two sorts of information: information gained in the special way that goes with that relation (first-person information, in the case of the SELF file), and information not gained in this way but concerning the same individual as information gained in that way.Other stable files include recognitional files (based upon lasting dispositions to recognize the object), files based on testimonial relations to objects we hear about in communication, and ‘encyclopedia entries’, that is, detached files based on higher-order ER relations which abstract from specific information channels.InMentalFilesI argue that the ‘indexical model’ applies to all these files, however stable they are.

    As far as linguistic indexicals are concerned, the critical features seem to me to be the following:

    (1) There aretwosemanticdimensions, corresponding to character and content, or to standing meaning and reference, and they map onto the type/token distinction.

    (2) Reference is determined throughcontextualrelationsto the token (hence indexicals are context-sensitive).

    (3) The standing meaning is ‘token-reflexive’—it reflects the relation between token and referent.

    Figure 1 below sums up the standard story regarding indexicals:

    Figure 1 The Indexical Model for Language

    This model, I argue, applies to thought.To be sure, the notion of conventional meaning does not apply in the mental realm, but the type/token distinction does apply.As far as mental files are concerned, they are typed according to the type of ER relation they exploit.Thus the SELF file exploits the relation in virtue of which one can gain information about oneself in a way in which one can gain information about no one else (as Frege puts it).My SELF file is not the same as yours, and they refer to different persons, of course, but they belong to the same type: They are both SELF files, unified by the common ER relation which is their function to exploit.We see that thefunctionof files—namely, informational exploitation of the relevant ER relation—plays the same role as the conventional meaning of indexicals: Through their functional role, mental file types map to types of ER relations, just as, through their linguistic meaning (their character), indexical types map to types of contextual relation between token and referent.The indexical model therefore applies to mental files, modulo the substitution of functional role for linguistic meaning (Figure 2).

    Figure 2 The Indexical Model for Thought

    If I am right, then there are ‘mental indexicals’, as Perry claimed.But there is room also for circumstance-relativity in thought, as Lewis claimed.To this (last) issue I now turn.

    6.IMPLICIT REPRESENTATION

    In the language case I have drawn a distinction between the explicit content of an utterance and the complete content which involves a situation of evaluation in addition to the explicit content.In the mental case, the mode/content distinction introduces something very similar, or so I claimed.

    What—following Searle (1983)—I call the ‘mode’ is what enables us to classify experiential states into types such asperceptions,memories, etc., quite independent of the content of the state (what is perceived, remembered, etc.).InPerspectivalThought, I argue that the mode determines the situation with respect to which the content of an experiential state is to be evaluated.Since the mode contributes in this way to the state’s complete content, the explicit content of the state need not possess absolute truth-conditions.InPerspectivalThought, indeed, I argue that the content of perception is a temporal proposition, true at certain times but not at others.That is so because the content of a perception is to be evaluated with respect to the situation of perception.The situation of perception includes the time of perception, and that is how the relevant time gets into the complete content: the perceptual state is veridical only if what the state represents is the caseatthetimeofperception.The time of the seeing is relevant to the evaluation of the visual experience, but it is not part of what is seen.

    The situation of perception involves not only a specific time, relevant to the evaluation of what is perceived, but also a certain (causal-epistemic) relation between the perceiver and what is perceived.A perception cannot be veridical unless that relation obtains, yet the relation is no more part ofwhatis perceived than the time of perception is.The subject does not perceive that he perceives, though he is aware of it: He perceives an external state of affairs, and, simply in virtue of being in such a perceptual state, is justified in assuming that he stands in a certain causal-epistemic relation—the perceptual relation—to the state of affairs which the state represents.

    On this picture, the complete content of the state is jointly determined by its (explicit) content and by its mode.The mode determines the situation with respect to which the content of the state is to be evaluated.In the case of perception, the content of the state is to be evaluated with respect to the situation of perception—a situation that is contemporaneous with the state, and which involves the subject of the state’s standing in a certain causal relation to what the state represents.So, when the subject sees Bill looking happy, Bill is explicitly represented, he is part of what is perceived broadly construed, while the time at which Bill looks happy is only implicitly represented, via the contribution of the perceptual mode.When, some time later, the subject remembers Bill looking happy, the content of his state is arguably the same, but the contribution of the mode is different.In the case of memory the mode determines that the content of the state is to be evaluated with respect to apastsituation of perception—a situation that isnotcontemporaneous with the state the remembering subject is in.So the temporal difference between perception and memory is not a difference in contentstrictosensu—a difference between what is perceived and what is remembered—but a difference in mode; a difference that affects thecompletecontent of the state, without affecting itsexplicitcontent.

    The mode’s contribution to the complete content corresponds to what the experiential stateimplicitlyrepresents.Thus a perception of Bob’s looking happy implicitly represents the time at which Bob looks happy.When it comes to thoughts in the first person—attitudesdese, to use Lewis’s terminology—we can also distinguish between the subject’s implicit involvement arising from the experiential mode’s contribution to complete content, from the subject’s explicit self-identification in first-person judgments.

    Consider the phenomenon of immunity to error through misidentification (IEM), to which I have devoted several pieces of work.If, without looking, the subject feels that his legs are crossed, the fact thathehimselfis the person whose legs are crossed is guaranteed by the fact that the information he gets about the position of his legs is gained ‘from inside’.I take the content of a proprioceptive experience to be nothing but a bodily condition; what makes the bodily condition in questionthesubject’sbodily condition is the mode of the experience—no information can be gained on the proprioceptive mode concerning the position of other people’s limbs.In other words, the mode imposes the subject of the state (at the time of the state) as the relevant circumstance of evaluation for the explicit content, namely the property of ‘having one’s legs crossed’ which is arguably the content of the proprioceptive state.No such thing happens when the subjectseesthe position of his limbs in the mirror; for the perceptual mode does not guarantee that the person whose limbs are seen is the subject.[注]What it guarantees, however, is that the person who sees is the subject, i.e.the person undergoing the visual experience.In this case, the subject has to explicitly identify himself as the person whose legs are crossed, and this gives rise to the possibility of ‘error through misidentification’.

    In this framework, as I said above, there is both mental indexicality in the strict sense and circumstance-relativity.There is mental indexicality in the strict sense when, on the side of explicit content, we find a concept of self through which the subject explicitly identifies himself as the bearer of this or that property.That is what, inPerspectivalThought, I call an ‘explicitdesethought’.For example, when I think that I was born in 1952, I explicitly identify myself.That must be so because there is no way in which I could acquire this piece of information ‘from inside’.The self’s involvement cannot come from the mode, in such cases, hence it must come from the content.When information about the position of one’s limbs is at issue, the situation is different: Such information can be gained from inside, and if it is, the subject’s involvement may be left implicit and determined by the experiential mode.It need not be left implicit, though: The subject may explicitly self-ascribe the bodily condition that is the content of his proprioceptive state.It follows that there are two types of explicitdesethoughts (Recanati forthcomingb): Those which display immunity to error through misidentification because the mode of the underlying experience is what justifies self-ascribing the predicated property, and those which are not so immune because the subject’s information about the position of his or her limbs is not gained from inside.The difference between the two cases corresponds to a difference in the subject’s grounds for his self-ascriptive judgment.

    What is it for the subject to explicitly think about oneself? It is to activate the SELF file.The SELF file is based on the first-person way of gaining information, but it is crucial that it can also be exercised in connection with information gained in another way.Mental files are concepts, and concepts satisfy what Evans calls the Generality Constraint:

    If a subject can be credited with the thought thataisF, then he must have the conceptual resources for entertaining the thought thataisG, for every property of beingGof which he has a conception.This is the condition that I call ‘The Generality Constraint’.(Evans 1982: 104)

    Translated into mental-file talk, the Generality Constraint says that a file should be hospitable to any information about the reference of the file, whether or not that piece of information is gained in the special way corresponding to the ER relation on which the file is based.Now the SELF file is based on the first-person way of gaining information and there is much information about myself that I cannot gain in this way.My date of birth is something I learn through communication, in the same way in which I learn my parents’ birthdates.In virtue of the Generality Constraint, it should be possible for that information to go into my SELF file.It follows that a file based on a certain ER relation contains two sorts of information: information gained in the special way that goes with that relation (first-person information, in the case of the SELF file), and information not gained in this way butconcerningthesameindividualasinformationgainedinthatway.Information about my birthdate is a case in point: I gain that information in a third-person way, through communication (as I might come to know anybody’s birthdate), but I take that piece of information to concern the same person about whom I also have direct first-person information, i.e.myself; so that information, too, goes into the SELF file.I am therefore able to exercise my SELF concept in thinking “I was born in 1952”.That information can go into the file because the file is ‘linked’ to other files based upon distinct ER relations.Whenever two files are linked, information from one file can flow freely into the other.(In the mental-file framework, identity judgments are accounted for in terms of linking between files.)

    It is because of that dual aspect of the SELF conceptquasatisfier of the Generality Constraint that there are two types of explicitdesethoughts: Those that are, and those that are not, immune to error through misidentification.When some information is gained from inside, that is, in virtue of the ER relation on which the SELF file is based, that information can only be about the subject: The way the information is gained determines in which file it goes.As a result, as Evans puts it,“there just does not appear to be a gap between the subject’s having information (or appearing to have information), in the appropriate way, that the property of beingFis instantiated, and his having information (or appearing to have information) thatheisF”(Evans 1982: 221).But when some information about ourselves is gained from outside, through linking, it goes into the SELF file only in virtue of a judgment of identity.The thought “I was born in 1952”can thus be seen as the product of two thoughts: the thought that a certain person, namely the person I hear about in a given episode of communication, was born in 1952, and the thought that I am the person talked about.The thought that I was born in 1952 thus turns out to be ‘identification-dependent’, in Evans terminology, and vulnerable to error through misidentification.

    ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

    I am grateful to Prof.Longgen Liu, Prof.Feng Yang, and Yuhuan Suo for suggesting that I should write a general review of my research in the philosophy of language forContemporaryForeignLanguagesStudies.I am especially indebted to Prof.Longgen Liu for making my booksLiteralMeaningandTruth-ConditionalPragmaticsavailable in translation to Chinese readers.Some of the research reported in this paper has received funding from the European Community’s Seventh Framework Programme FP7/2007-2013 under grant agreement n° FP7-238128 and ERC grant agreement n° 229441—CCC.

    REFERENCES

    Austin,J.1975.HowtoDoThingswithWords(2ndedition).Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Bach,K.andHarnish,M.1979.LinguisticCommunicationandSpeechActs.Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Bar-Hillel,Y.1954.IndexicalExpressions.Reprinted in Bar-Hillel, 1970, pp.69-88.

    Bar-Hillel,Y.1970.AspectsofLanguage.Jerusalem: The Magnes Press.

    Barwise,J.andJ.Etchemendy.1987.TheLiar.New York: Oxford University Press.

    Evans,G.1982.TheVarietiesofReference(edited by J.McDowell).Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Evans,G.1985.‘Does Tense Logic Rest on a Mistake?’ in G.Evans (ed.):CollectedPapers.Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp.343-63.

    Frege,G.1967.KleineSchriften(edited by I.Angelelli).Hildesheim: Olms.

    Grice,P.1957.‘Meaning,’PhilosophicalReview66: 377-88.

    Grice,P.1989.StudiesintheWayofWords.Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Kaplan,D.1989.‘Demonstratives’ in J.Almog, H.Wettstein and J.Perry (eds.):ThemesfromKaplan.New York: Oxford University Press, pp.481-563.

    K?lbel,M.andM.Garcia-Carpintero(eds.).2008.RelativeTruth.Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Lewis,D.1979.‘AttitudesDeDictoandDeSe,’PhilosophicalReview88: 513-43.

    Lewis,D.1980.‘Index, Context, and Content’ in S.Kanger and S.?hman (eds.):PhilosophyandGrammar.Dordrecht: Reidel, pp.79-100.

    Malinowski,B.1923.‘The Problem of Meaning in Primitive Languages,’ supplement to C.Ogden and I.A.Richards,TheMeaningofMeaning(10thedition).London: Routledge, 1949, pp.296-336.

    Perry,J.1977.‘Frege on Demonstratives,’PhilosophicalReview86: 474-97.Reprinted, with a postscript, in Perry, 1993, pp.3-32.

    Perry,J.1993.TheProblemoftheEssentialIndexicalandOtherEssays.New York: Oxford University Press.

    Perry,J.2002.Identity,PersonalIdentity,andtheSelf.Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Recanati,F.1987.MeaningandForce.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Recanati,F.1989.‘The Pragmatics of What is Said,’MindandLanguage4: 295-329.Reprinted in Davis, S.(ed.):Pragmatics:AReader.Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991, pp.97-120.

    Recanati,F.1993.DirectReference:FromLanguagetoThought.Oxford: Blackwell.

    Recanati,F.2000.OratioObliqua,OratioRecta.Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Recanati,F.2004.LiteralMeaning.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Recanati,F.2007.PerspectivalThought.Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Recanati,F.2010.Truth-ConditionalPragmatics.Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Recanati,F.(forthcominga).MentalFiles.

    Recanati,F.(forthcomingb).‘Immunity to error through misidentification: what it is and where it comes from’ in S.Prosser and F.Recanati (eds.):ImmunitytoErrorthroughMisidentification:NewEssays.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Searle,J.1969.SpeechActs.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Searle,J.1983.Intentionality.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Sperber,D.andD.Wilson.1986.Relevance:CommunicationandCognition.Oxford: Blackwell.

    Strawson,P.1964.IntentionandConventioninSpeechActs.Reprinted in Strawson,1971, pp.149-69.

    Strawson,P.1971.Logico-LinguisticPapers.London: Methuen.

    Tsohatzidis,S.(ed.) 1994.FoundationsofSpeechActTheory:PhilosophicalandLinguisticPerspectives.London: Routledge.

    久久人人爽人人片av| 成人亚洲欧美一区二区av| 黑人欧美特级aaaaaa片| 午夜福利乱码中文字幕| 亚洲伊人久久精品综合| 国产深夜福利视频在线观看| 69精品国产乱码久久久| 女人被躁到高潮嗷嗷叫费观| 最黄视频免费看| 麻豆乱淫一区二区| 蜜臀久久99精品久久宅男| 婷婷色综合大香蕉| kizo精华| 国产亚洲最大av| 亚洲精品一二三| 天堂8中文在线网| 色5月婷婷丁香| 精品第一国产精品| 国产探花极品一区二区| 啦啦啦视频在线资源免费观看| 99国产精品免费福利视频| xxxhd国产人妻xxx| 亚洲中文av在线| 午夜老司机福利剧场| 午夜福利在线观看免费完整高清在| 国内精品宾馆在线| 欧美精品人与动牲交sv欧美| 欧美精品亚洲一区二区| 亚洲av国产av综合av卡| 久久99热6这里只有精品| 国产精品一国产av| 18禁动态无遮挡网站| 极品人妻少妇av视频| 一个人免费看片子| 国产精品国产三级专区第一集| 黄色配什么色好看| 亚洲欧美一区二区三区黑人 | 国产欧美日韩一区二区三区在线| 99久久精品国产国产毛片| 免费大片18禁| 国产av码专区亚洲av| 久久久久国产精品人妻一区二区| 69精品国产乱码久久久| 久久久久久久亚洲中文字幕| 精品一区在线观看国产| 亚洲国产日韩一区二区| 人妻人人澡人人爽人人| 亚洲av中文av极速乱| 成年av动漫网址| 91精品伊人久久大香线蕉| 精品一区二区三区视频在线| 久久精品国产亚洲av天美| a级片在线免费高清观看视频| 性高湖久久久久久久久免费观看| 欧美xxⅹ黑人| 美女主播在线视频| 在线观看三级黄色| av在线播放精品| 曰老女人黄片| 中文字幕免费在线视频6| 丝袜喷水一区| 一本一本久久a久久精品综合妖精 国产伦在线观看视频一区 | 国产日韩欧美视频二区| 黑人巨大精品欧美一区二区蜜桃 | 国产国语露脸激情在线看| www.熟女人妻精品国产 | 全区人妻精品视频| 精品人妻偷拍中文字幕| 亚洲综合色惰| 精品午夜福利在线看| 中文字幕av电影在线播放| 亚洲欧美中文字幕日韩二区| 极品少妇高潮喷水抽搐| 精品国产一区二区三区四区第35| 中国美白少妇内射xxxbb| 天堂中文最新版在线下载| 亚洲熟女精品中文字幕| 日韩中文字幕视频在线看片| 一区二区三区四区激情视频| 热99国产精品久久久久久7| 日韩一区二区三区影片| 国产乱人偷精品视频| 精品视频人人做人人爽| 女人久久www免费人成看片| 国产黄色免费在线视频| 精品一区二区三区四区五区乱码 | 亚洲av国产av综合av卡| 国产极品粉嫩免费观看在线| 午夜激情久久久久久久| 国产精品久久久久久av不卡| 亚洲婷婷狠狠爱综合网| 99久久精品国产国产毛片| 老司机亚洲免费影院| 99久国产av精品国产电影| 成人二区视频| 免费少妇av软件| 日韩在线高清观看一区二区三区| 肉色欧美久久久久久久蜜桃| 狠狠婷婷综合久久久久久88av| 国产精品偷伦视频观看了| 精品一区二区免费观看| 久久人人爽av亚洲精品天堂| 丰满少妇做爰视频| 在线观看www视频免费| 亚洲精品一区蜜桃| 一本一本久久a久久精品综合妖精 国产伦在线观看视频一区 | 黑人巨大精品欧美一区二区蜜桃 | 亚洲国产精品一区三区| 春色校园在线视频观看| 国产精品久久久久久精品古装| 国产日韩欧美在线精品| 少妇高潮的动态图| 亚洲一区二区三区欧美精品| 中文精品一卡2卡3卡4更新| 人妻少妇偷人精品九色| 97超碰精品成人国产| 国产精品偷伦视频观看了| 中文字幕av电影在线播放| 男女午夜视频在线观看 | 天堂俺去俺来也www色官网| 欧美激情国产日韩精品一区| 人人妻人人澡人人看| 一级毛片我不卡| 欧美97在线视频| 国产黄色免费在线视频| 精品卡一卡二卡四卡免费| 久久久国产欧美日韩av| 日产精品乱码卡一卡2卡三| 观看美女的网站| 久久人人97超碰香蕉20202| 精品国产一区二区三区久久久樱花| 亚洲综合色网址| 亚洲精品成人av观看孕妇| 色5月婷婷丁香| 亚洲色图 男人天堂 中文字幕 | 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 日韩一区二区视频免费看| 成年美女黄网站色视频大全免费| 亚洲综合色惰| a级毛色黄片| 少妇高潮的动态图| 国国产精品蜜臀av免费| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠躁躁| 日韩av不卡免费在线播放| 亚洲精品久久午夜乱码| 新久久久久国产一级毛片| 满18在线观看网站| 亚洲,一卡二卡三卡| 亚洲精品一区蜜桃| 只有这里有精品99| 99久久精品国产国产毛片| 国产精品国产av在线观看| 欧美人与性动交α欧美精品济南到 | 亚洲欧美精品自产自拍| 黄色怎么调成土黄色| 国产乱人偷精品视频| 精品福利永久在线观看| 综合色丁香网| 高清在线视频一区二区三区| 久久免费观看电影| 王馨瑶露胸无遮挡在线观看| 中国美白少妇内射xxxbb| 搡女人真爽免费视频火全软件| 久久国内精品自在自线图片| 亚洲在久久综合| 国产成人免费观看mmmm| 久久精品久久久久久久性| 久久久久久久久久人人人人人人| 两个人看的免费小视频| 午夜影院在线不卡| 国产一区二区在线观看日韩| 亚洲人与动物交配视频| 精品国产露脸久久av麻豆| www.熟女人妻精品国产 | 亚洲综合色网址| 妹子高潮喷水视频| 人成视频在线观看免费观看| 黄色怎么调成土黄色| 久久久国产欧美日韩av| 日本午夜av视频| 国语对白做爰xxxⅹ性视频网站| 精品一区二区三卡| 国产熟女午夜一区二区三区| 51国产日韩欧美| 精品人妻熟女毛片av久久网站| 亚洲av男天堂| 亚洲成人一二三区av| 国产精品久久久久久久电影| 最近中文字幕高清免费大全6| 久久久a久久爽久久v久久| 亚洲精品视频女| 久久韩国三级中文字幕| 亚洲人成网站在线观看播放| 黑人高潮一二区| 欧美成人午夜精品| 男女免费视频国产| 久久97久久精品| 精品国产一区二区三区四区第35| 精品久久久久久电影网| 欧美3d第一页| 国产免费福利视频在线观看| 少妇猛男粗大的猛烈进出视频| 精品一区二区三卡| 免费播放大片免费观看视频在线观看| 99热全是精品| 男女免费视频国产| 久久国产亚洲av麻豆专区| 精品国产一区二区三区四区第35| 少妇人妻久久综合中文| 免费看av在线观看网站| a级毛片在线看网站| 少妇猛男粗大的猛烈进出视频| 久久婷婷青草| 七月丁香在线播放| 啦啦啦啦在线视频资源| 日韩av在线免费看完整版不卡| 国产成人免费无遮挡视频| 精品一品国产午夜福利视频| 一本色道久久久久久精品综合| 啦啦啦啦在线视频资源| 久久久亚洲精品成人影院| av卡一久久| 久久毛片免费看一区二区三区| 久久这里只有精品19| 少妇 在线观看| 久久久久久久久久久免费av| 免费大片18禁| 80岁老熟妇乱子伦牲交| 国产男人的电影天堂91| 久久久久久人人人人人| 大香蕉久久成人网| 国产精品一区www在线观看| 成人亚洲精品一区在线观看| www.熟女人妻精品国产 | 亚洲精品国产色婷婷电影| 韩国精品一区二区三区 | 国产在线一区二区三区精| freevideosex欧美| 亚洲精品国产av成人精品| 日韩成人伦理影院| 欧美另类一区| 日韩电影二区| 亚洲av中文av极速乱| 青春草亚洲视频在线观看| 天堂俺去俺来也www色官网| 日韩成人伦理影院| 在线观看免费日韩欧美大片| 国产片内射在线| 熟女人妻精品中文字幕| 国产成人午夜福利电影在线观看| 国产精品无大码| 亚洲精品国产色婷婷电影| 男男h啪啪无遮挡| a级毛片黄视频| 晚上一个人看的免费电影| 男女无遮挡免费网站观看| 日韩人妻精品一区2区三区| 久久午夜综合久久蜜桃| 97精品久久久久久久久久精品| 侵犯人妻中文字幕一二三四区| 高清毛片免费看| 在线观看人妻少妇| 欧美激情 高清一区二区三区| 人体艺术视频欧美日本| 自拍欧美九色日韩亚洲蝌蚪91| 欧美xxxx性猛交bbbb| 亚洲精华国产精华液的使用体验| 大陆偷拍与自拍| 日韩制服骚丝袜av| 99久久精品国产国产毛片| 王馨瑶露胸无遮挡在线观看| 91在线精品国自产拍蜜月| 91久久精品国产一区二区三区| 18禁裸乳无遮挡动漫免费视频| 中文字幕人妻熟女乱码| 免费高清在线观看视频在线观看| 国产免费一级a男人的天堂| 免费高清在线观看日韩| 精品酒店卫生间| 深夜精品福利| av视频免费观看在线观看| 永久免费av网站大全| 亚洲精品乱久久久久久| 亚洲一区二区三区欧美精品| 人妻系列 视频| 热re99久久国产66热| 看免费av毛片| 亚洲国产精品一区三区| 激情五月婷婷亚洲| 一级片'在线观看视频| 桃花免费在线播放| 精品一区二区三区四区五区乱码 | 97人妻天天添夜夜摸| 亚洲av免费高清在线观看| 性色avwww在线观看| 91精品伊人久久大香线蕉| 久久精品久久精品一区二区三区| 久久久久人妻精品一区果冻| 一级毛片电影观看| 日韩av免费高清视频| 精品久久蜜臀av无| 亚洲欧美成人综合另类久久久| 欧美老熟妇乱子伦牲交| 日韩欧美一区视频在线观看| 久久久久久久亚洲中文字幕| 男女午夜视频在线观看 | freevideosex欧美| 视频在线观看一区二区三区| 久久免费观看电影| 国产永久视频网站| 母亲3免费完整高清在线观看 | 亚洲精品成人av观看孕妇| 51国产日韩欧美| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区| 9热在线视频观看99| a 毛片基地| 国产精品99久久99久久久不卡 | 久久精品熟女亚洲av麻豆精品| 欧美97在线视频| 亚洲三级黄色毛片| 日韩精品免费视频一区二区三区 | 捣出白浆h1v1| 国产一区二区激情短视频 | 视频在线观看一区二区三区| 汤姆久久久久久久影院中文字幕| 亚洲精品久久久久久婷婷小说| 亚洲精品自拍成人| 母亲3免费完整高清在线观看 | 欧美亚洲日本最大视频资源| 如何舔出高潮| 中文字幕制服av| 久久久久久人妻| 久久精品国产a三级三级三级| av黄色大香蕉| 99久久人妻综合| av在线老鸭窝| 日韩视频在线欧美| 80岁老熟妇乱子伦牲交| 宅男免费午夜| 亚洲精品美女久久久久99蜜臀 | 久久久久久久大尺度免费视频| 国产欧美日韩一区二区三区在线| 丝瓜视频免费看黄片| 日本91视频免费播放| 久久国产精品男人的天堂亚洲 | 日韩不卡一区二区三区视频在线| 人人妻人人澡人人看| 最近最新中文字幕免费大全7| 精品午夜福利在线看| 多毛熟女@视频| 人人妻人人添人人爽欧美一区卜| 亚洲色图综合在线观看| av国产久精品久网站免费入址| 国内精品宾馆在线| 欧美xxxx性猛交bbbb| 国产无遮挡羞羞视频在线观看| 午夜精品国产一区二区电影| 极品少妇高潮喷水抽搐| 久久精品熟女亚洲av麻豆精品| 国产精品不卡视频一区二区| 岛国毛片在线播放| 国产有黄有色有爽视频| 亚洲欧美成人综合另类久久久| av不卡在线播放| 免费人成在线观看视频色| 欧美xxⅹ黑人| 国产成人欧美| 久久久久久久久久成人| 国产一区二区三区av在线| 午夜免费鲁丝| 免费黄网站久久成人精品| 久久国产精品男人的天堂亚洲 | 色吧在线观看| 久久影院123| 午夜老司机福利剧场| 少妇人妻精品综合一区二区| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠躁躁| 久久婷婷青草| 五月开心婷婷网| 永久免费av网站大全| 免费观看a级毛片全部| 亚洲精品色激情综合| 人人澡人人妻人| 最近手机中文字幕大全| 99热这里只有是精品在线观看| 少妇高潮的动态图| 精品午夜福利在线看| 99热6这里只有精品| 久久av网站| 美女主播在线视频| 久久国产亚洲av麻豆专区| 高清毛片免费看| 99国产综合亚洲精品| 精品久久蜜臀av无| 韩国av在线不卡| 在线观看一区二区三区激情| 精品人妻熟女毛片av久久网站| 亚洲国产精品一区二区三区在线| 成人手机av| 又粗又硬又长又爽又黄的视频| 久久精品久久精品一区二区三区| 国产片特级美女逼逼视频| 丝袜在线中文字幕| 久久精品aⅴ一区二区三区四区 | 美国免费a级毛片| 国产无遮挡羞羞视频在线观看| 国产成人精品无人区| 在线观看免费高清a一片| 国产毛片在线视频| 美女大奶头黄色视频| 国产成人91sexporn| 久久综合国产亚洲精品| 高清欧美精品videossex| 欧美亚洲日本最大视频资源| 国产在线一区二区三区精| 久久人人97超碰香蕉20202| 欧美精品高潮呻吟av久久| 一级爰片在线观看| 九草在线视频观看| 这个男人来自地球电影免费观看 | 男人爽女人下面视频在线观看| 丝瓜视频免费看黄片| 色5月婷婷丁香| 交换朋友夫妻互换小说| 日日撸夜夜添| 午夜免费鲁丝| 一级黄片播放器| 免费少妇av软件| 国产成人精品在线电影| 香蕉国产在线看| 亚洲精品国产色婷婷电影| 亚洲av免费高清在线观看| 欧美成人午夜免费资源| 亚洲国产精品999| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠久久av| 桃花免费在线播放| 少妇猛男粗大的猛烈进出视频| 国产乱来视频区| 国产淫语在线视频| 精品熟女少妇av免费看| 亚洲国产av新网站| 国精品久久久久久国模美| 国产精品一二三区在线看| 久久精品aⅴ一区二区三区四区 | 水蜜桃什么品种好| 免费少妇av软件| 国产av码专区亚洲av| 国产精品秋霞免费鲁丝片| 久久久久久久精品精品| 欧美成人午夜精品| 欧美变态另类bdsm刘玥| 人成视频在线观看免费观看| 各种免费的搞黄视频| 午夜91福利影院| 九九爱精品视频在线观看| 久久精品国产亚洲av涩爱| 超色免费av| 男女高潮啪啪啪动态图| 黄色视频在线播放观看不卡| 男人添女人高潮全过程视频| 亚洲精品aⅴ在线观看| 国产精品人妻久久久影院| 婷婷色综合www| 国产色爽女视频免费观看| 99精国产麻豆久久婷婷| 久久这里只有精品19| 精品少妇内射三级| 亚洲av在线观看美女高潮| 久久久国产精品麻豆| 日韩不卡一区二区三区视频在线| 日日爽夜夜爽网站| 天天躁夜夜躁狠狠躁躁| 午夜av观看不卡| 午夜免费鲁丝| 晚上一个人看的免费电影| 国产在线视频一区二区| 99香蕉大伊视频| 高清不卡的av网站| 高清毛片免费看| 欧美最新免费一区二区三区| 草草在线视频免费看| 精品国产国语对白av| 精品亚洲成国产av| 大话2 男鬼变身卡| 有码 亚洲区| 侵犯人妻中文字幕一二三四区| 国产成人午夜福利电影在线观看| 亚洲一区二区三区欧美精品| 久久久久人妻精品一区果冻| 青春草国产在线视频| 人妻一区二区av| 哪个播放器可以免费观看大片| 色视频在线一区二区三区| 狠狠精品人妻久久久久久综合| 波野结衣二区三区在线| 桃花免费在线播放| 五月天丁香电影| 一区二区日韩欧美中文字幕 | 成人国产麻豆网| 性色avwww在线观看| 巨乳人妻的诱惑在线观看| 日韩av不卡免费在线播放| 精品第一国产精品| 国产欧美日韩一区二区三区在线| 久久女婷五月综合色啪小说| 日韩大片免费观看网站| 美女国产高潮福利片在线看| 亚洲精华国产精华液的使用体验| 欧美精品一区二区免费开放| 国产1区2区3区精品| av在线老鸭窝| 91午夜精品亚洲一区二区三区| 黑人欧美特级aaaaaa片| 狠狠精品人妻久久久久久综合| 最近中文字幕2019免费版| 亚洲精品乱久久久久久| 人妻少妇偷人精品九色| 国产成人一区二区在线| 七月丁香在线播放| 黑人巨大精品欧美一区二区蜜桃 | 最近的中文字幕免费完整| 国产男女超爽视频在线观看| 亚洲av电影在线观看一区二区三区| 午夜影院在线不卡| 亚洲av成人精品一二三区| 免费看av在线观看网站| 亚洲av国产av综合av卡| 久久人人爽人人片av| 不卡视频在线观看欧美| 各种免费的搞黄视频| 99九九在线精品视频| 99久久人妻综合| 国产成人精品无人区| 亚洲av男天堂| 成年人午夜在线观看视频| 久久久久久久久久成人| 女人精品久久久久毛片| 国产成人aa在线观看| 国产成人精品福利久久| 青青草视频在线视频观看| 在线天堂中文资源库| 久久97久久精品| 最近中文字幕2019免费版| 精品一区二区三区视频在线| 亚洲精品日韩在线中文字幕| 啦啦啦啦在线视频资源| 国产欧美日韩综合在线一区二区| 欧美日韩av久久| 女性生殖器流出的白浆| 黑人猛操日本美女一级片| 黑人巨大精品欧美一区二区蜜桃 | 亚洲精品av麻豆狂野| 男女无遮挡免费网站观看| 欧美bdsm另类| a级毛片黄视频| 国产免费现黄频在线看| 精品少妇内射三级| 99国产综合亚洲精品| 亚洲国产最新在线播放| 90打野战视频偷拍视频| 亚洲欧美日韩卡通动漫| 深夜精品福利| 中国国产av一级| 国产精品国产av在线观看| 日本猛色少妇xxxxx猛交久久| 亚洲第一av免费看| 爱豆传媒免费全集在线观看| 老女人水多毛片| 亚洲精品乱久久久久久| 精品99又大又爽又粗少妇毛片| 久久久久久久久久久久大奶| 9191精品国产免费久久| 亚洲国产精品999| 国产亚洲欧美精品永久| 久久精品国产a三级三级三级| 欧美日韩成人在线一区二区| 热99国产精品久久久久久7| 伦理电影大哥的女人| av天堂久久9| 男人添女人高潮全过程视频| 国产精品秋霞免费鲁丝片| 韩国高清视频一区二区三区| 亚洲精品aⅴ在线观看| 成人无遮挡网站| 日本黄色日本黄色录像| 精品一区在线观看国产| 午夜影院在线不卡| 亚洲国产av影院在线观看| 成人二区视频| 亚洲精品视频女| 欧美国产精品va在线观看不卡| 国产白丝娇喘喷水9色精品| 成人18禁高潮啪啪吃奶动态图| 精品一区二区三卡| 一级毛片 在线播放| 中文字幕制服av| 中文欧美无线码| 侵犯人妻中文字幕一二三四区| 男女免费视频国产| 久久午夜福利片| www.av在线官网国产| 国产精品一区二区在线不卡| 免费少妇av软件| 99久久中文字幕三级久久日本| 中文字幕免费在线视频6| 香蕉国产在线看| 国产精品国产三级国产专区5o| 成人毛片a级毛片在线播放| 一本大道久久a久久精品| 色94色欧美一区二区| 亚洲精品av麻豆狂野| 国产探花极品一区二区| 久久影院123| 免费看不卡的av| av一本久久久久|